SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

Civic Education

In its broadest definition, “civic education” means all the processes that affect people’s beliefs, commitments, capabilities, and actions as members or prospective members of communities. Civic education need not be intentional or deliberate; institutions and communities transmit values and norms without meaning to. It may not be beneficial: sometimes people are civically educated in ways that disempower them or impart harmful values and goals. It is certainly not limited to schooling and the education of children and youth. Families, governments, religions, and mass media are just some of the institutions involved in civic education, understood as a lifelong process. [ 1 ] A rightly famous example is Tocqueville’s often quoted observation that local political engagement is a form of civic education: “Town meetings are to liberty what primary schools are to science; they bring it within the people’s reach, they teach men how to use and how to enjoy it.”

Nevertheless, most scholarship that uses the phrase “civic education” investigates deliberate programs of instruction within schools or colleges, in contrast to paideia (see below) and other forms of citizen preparation that involve a whole culture and last a lifetime. There are several good reasons for the emphasis on schools. First, empirical evidence shows that civic habits and values are relatively easily to influence and change while people are still young, so schooling can be effective when other efforts to educate citizens would fail (Sherrod, Flanagan, and Youniss, 2002). Another reason is that schools in many countries have an explicit mission to educate students for citizenship. As Amy Gutmann points out, school-based education is our most deliberate form of human instruction (1987, 15). Defining the purposes and methods of civic education in schools is a worthy topic of public debate. Nevertheless, it is important not to lose sight of the fact that civic education takes place at all stages of life and in many venues other than schools.

Whether defined narrowly or broadly, civic education raises empirical questions: What causes people to develop durable habits, values, knowledge, and skills relevant to their membership in communities? Are people affected differently if they vary by age, social or cultural background, and starting assumptions? For example, does a high school civics course have lasting effects on various kinds of students, and what would make it more effective?

From the 1960s until the 1980s, empirical questions concerning civic education were relatively neglected, mainly because of a prevailing assumption that intentional programs would not have significant and durable effects, given the more powerful influences of social class and ideology (Cook, 1985). Since then, many research studies and program evaluations have found substantial effects, and most social scientists who study the topic now believe that educational practices, such as discussion of controversial issues, hands-on action, and reflection, can influence students (Sherrod, Torney-Purta & Flanagan, 2010).

The philosophical questions have been less explored, but they are essential. For example:

Who has the full rights and obligations of a citizen? This question is especially contested with regard to children, immigrant aliens, and individuals who have been convicted of felonies.

In what communities ought we see ourselves as citizens? The nation-state is not the only candidate; some people see themselves as citizens of local geographical communities, organizations, movements, loosely-defined groups, or even the world as a whole.

What responsibilities does a citizen of each kind of community have? Do all members of each community have the same responsibilities, or ought there be significant differences, for example, between elders and children, or between leaders and other members?

What is the relationship between a good regime and good citizenship? Aristotle held that there were several acceptable types of regimes, and each needed different kinds of citizens. That makes the question of good citizenship relative to the regime-type. But other theorists have argued for particular combinations of regime and citizen competence. For example, classical liberals endorsed regimes that would make relatively modest demands on citizens, both because they were skeptical that people could rise to higher demands and because they wanted to safeguard individual liberty against the state. Civic republicans have seen a certain kind of citizenship--highly active and deliberative--as constitutive of a good life, and therefore recommend a republican regime because it permits good citizenship.

Who may decide what constitutes good citizenship? If we consider, for example, students enrolled in public schools in the United States, should the decision about what values, habits, and capabilities they should learn belong to their parents, their teachers, the children themselves, the local community, the local or state government, or the nation-state? We may reach different conclusions when thinking about 5-year-olds and adult college students. As Sheldon Wolin warned: “…[T]he inherent danger…is that the identity given to the collectivity by those who exercise power will reflect the needs of power rather than the political possibilities of a complex collectivity” (1989, 13). For some regimes—fascist or communist, for example—this is not perceived as a danger at all but, instead, the very purpose of their forms of civic education. In democracies, the question is more complex because public institutions may have to teach people to be good democratic citizens, but they can decide to do so in ways that reinforce the power of the state and reduce freedom.

What means of civic education are ethically appropriate? It might, for example, be effective to punish students who fail to memorize patriotic statements, or to pay students for community service, but the ethics of those approaches would be controversial. An educator might engage students in open discussions of current events because of a commitment to treating them as autonomous agents, regardless of the consequences. As with other topics, the proper relationship between means and ends is contested.

These questions are rarely treated together as part of comprehensive theories of civic education; instead, they arise in passing in works about politics or education. Some of these questions have never been much explored by professional philosophers, but they arise frequently in public debates about citizenship.

1.1 Ancient Greece

1.2 classical liberalism, 1.3 rousseau: toward progressive education, 1.4 mill: education through political participation, 1.5 early civic education in the united states, 2.1 the state, parents, and children in liberal democracies, 2.2 social capital, 2.3 deliberative democracy, 2.4 public work, 3.1 good persons and good citizens, 3.2 spectrum of virtues, 4.1 service learning, 4.2 action civics, 4.3 civic education through discussion, 4.4 john dewey: school as community, 4.5 liberation pedagogy, 5. cosmopolitan education, works cited, works to consult, other internet resources, related entries, 1. the good citizen: historical conceptions.

“As far back as evidence can be found—and virtually without exception—young adults seem to have been less attached to civic life than their parents and grandparents.” [ 2 ] That is not evidence of decline--although it is often read as such--but rather indicates that becoming a citizen is a developmental process. It must be taught and learned. Most if not all societies recognize a need to educate youth to be “civic-minded”; that is, to think and care about the welfare of the community (the commonweal or civitas ) and not simply about their own individual well-being. Sometimes, civic education is also intended to make all citizens, or at least prospective leaders, effective as citizens or to reduce disparities in political power by giving everyone the knowledge, confidence, and skills they need to participate. This section briefly introduces several conceptions of civic education that have been influential in the history of the West. [ 3 ]

The ancient Greek city state or polis was thought to be an educational community, expressed by the Greek term paideia . The purpose of political—that is civic or city—life was the self-development of the citizens. This meant more than just education, which is how paideia is usually translated. Education for the Greeks involved a deeply formative and life-long process whose goal was for each person (read: man) to be an asset to his friends, to his family, and, most important, to the polis.

Becoming such an asset necessitated internalizing and living up to the highest ethical ideals of the community. So paideia included education in the arts, philosophy and rhetoric, history, science, and mathematics; training in sports and warfare; enculturation or learning of the city’s religious, social, political, and professional customs and training to participate in them; and the development of one’s moral character through the virtues. Above all, the person should have a keen sense of duty to the city. Every aspect of Greek culture in the Classical Age—from the arts to politics and athletics—was devoted to the development of personal powers in public service.

Paideia was inseparable from another Greek concept: arete or excellence, especially excellence of reputation but also goodness and excellence in all aspects of life. Together paideia and arête form one process of self-development, which is nothing other than civic-development. Thus one could only develop himself in politics, through participation in the activities of the polis; and as individuals developed the characteristics of virtue, so would the polis itself become more virtuous and excellent.

All persons, whatever their occupations or tasks, were teachers, and the purpose of education—which was political life itself—was to develop a greater (a nobler, stronger, more virtuous) public community. So politics was more than regulating or ordering the affairs of the community; it was also a “school” for ordering the lives—internal and external—of the citizens. Therefore, the practice of Athenian democratic politics was not only a means of engendering good policies for the city, but it was also a “curriculum” for the intellectual, moral, and civic education of her citizens. “…[A]sk in general what great benefit the state derives from the training by which it educates its citizens, and the reply will be perfectly straightforward. The good education they have received will make them good men…” (Plato, Laws , 641b7–10). Indeed, later in the Laws the Athenian remarks that education should be designed to produce the desire to become “perfect citizens” who know, preceding Aristotle, “how to rule and be ruled” (643e4–6).

Ancient and medieval thinkers generally assumed that good government and good citizenship were intimately related, because a regime would degenerate unless its people actively and virtuously supported it. Aristotle regarded his Politics and his Ethics as part of the same subject. In his view, a city-state could not be just and strong unless its people were virtuous, and men could not exercise the political virtues (which were intrinsically admirable, dignified, and satisfying) unless they lived in a just polity. Civic virtue was especially important in a democratic or mixed regime, but even in a monarchy or oligarchy, people were expected to sustain the political community.

Today, the view that the best life is one of active participation in a community that relies on and encourages active engagement is often called “civic republicanism,” and it has been developed by authors like Wolin (1989), Barber (1992) and Hannah Arendt.

Classical liberal thinkers, however, saw serious drawbacks to making good government dependent on widespread civic virtue. First, any demanding and universal system of moral education would be incompatible with individual freedom. If, for example the state forced people to enroll their children in public schools in order to create good citizens, it would hamper parents and young people’s individual freedom.

The second problem was more practical. States did not have a very good record of producing moral virtue in rulers or subjects. Mandatory church membership, state-subsidized education, and even public spectacles of torture and execution did not reliably prevent corruption, sedition and other private behavior injurious to the community.

Thomas Hobbes is sometimes described as a forerunner of liberalism (despite his advocacy of absolute monarchy) because he held a dim view of human nature and thought that the way to prevent political disaster was to design the government right, not to try to improve civic virtue. He also held that a good government was one that permitted people to live their own lives safely. Another strong critic of the idea that a good society depended on civic virtue was Bernard Mandeville, who wrote a famous 1705 poem entitled, “The Fable of The Bees: or, Private Vices, Public Benefits.” Mandeville argued that a good society could arise from sheer individual self-interest if it was organized appropriately.

Other classical liberal thinkers typically favored some degree of civic education and civic virtue, even as they proposed limitations on the state and a strong private sphere to reduce the dependence of the regime on civic virtue. In other words, they steered a middle course between pure classical liberalism and civic republicanism. For example, in his “Instructions for the conduct of a young Gentleman, as to religion and government,” John Locke wrote that a gentleman’s “proper calling is the service of his country, and so is most properly concerned in moral and political knowledge; and thus the studies which more immediately belong to his calling are those which treat of virtues and vices, of civil society and the arts of government, and will take in also law and history.” That was an argument for civic education. But it appeared in a minor, unpublished fragment (Locke 1703: 350). Civic education was not a significant theme in Locke’s important treatise Some Thoughts Concerning Education (1693), which was more about teaching individuals to be free and responsible in their private lives. Likewise, the emphasis of his political writing was on limiting the power of the state and protecting private rights.

James Madison hoped for some degree of civic virtue in the people and especially in their representatives. He endorsed “the great republican principle, that the people will have the virtue and intelligence to select men of virtue and wisdom. Is there no virtue among us? If there be not, we are in a wretched situation. No theoretical checks--no form of government can render us secure” (Madison, 1788, 11:163) On the other hand, Madison proposed a whole series of reforms that would make government proof against the various vices that seemed to be “sown in the nature of man” (Madison, Hamilton, and Jay, Federalist 10). These tools included constitutional limitations on the overall power and scope of government; independent judges with power of review; elections with relatively broad franchise; and above all, checks and balances.

Madison explained that republics should be designed for people of moderate virtue, such as might be found in real societies. “If men were angels, no government would be necessary. If angels were to govern men, neither external nor internal controuls on government would be necessary.” Unfortunately, neither citizens nor rulers could be counted on to act like angels; but good government was possible anyway, as long as the constitution provided appropriate controls.

The main “external controul” in a republic was the vote, which made powerful men accountable to those they ruled. However, voting was not enough, especially since the voters themselves might lack virtue and wisdom. “A dependence on the people is no doubt the primary controul on the government; but experience has taught mankind the necessity of auxiliary precautions.” In general, Madison’s “auxiliary precautions” involved dividing power among separate institutions and giving them the ability to check one another.

This policy of supplying by opposite and rival interests, the defect of better motives, might be traced through the whole system of human affairs, private as well as public. We see it particularly displayed in all the subordinate distributions of power; where the constant aim is to divide and arrange the several offices in such a manner as that each may be a check on the other; that the private interest of every individual may be a centinel over the public rights. These inventions of prudence cannot be less requisite in the distribution of the supreme powers of the state. (Madison, Hamilton, and Jay, Federalist 51)

Although ancient Athens instituted democracy, her most famous philosophers—Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle—were not great champions of it. At best they were ambiguous about democracy; at worst, they were hostile toward it. The earliest unadulterated champion of democracy, a “dreamer of democracy,” was undoubtedly Rousseau. Yet Rousseau had his doubts that men could be good men and simultaneously good citizens. A good man for Rousseau is a natural man, with the attributes of freedom, independence, equality, happiness, sympathy, and love-of-self ( amour de soi ) found prior to society in the state of nature. Thus society could do little but corrupt such a man.

Still, Rousseau recognized that life in society is unavoidable, and so civic education or learning to function well in society is also unavoidable. The ideal for Rousseau is for men to act morally and yet retain as much of their naturalness as possible. Only in this way can a man retain his freedom; and only if a man follows those rules that he prescribes for himself—that is, only if a man is self-ruling—can he remain free: “…[E]ach individual…obeys no one but himself and remains as free as before [society]” (1988, 60).

Yet prescribing those rules is not a subjective or selfish act. It is a moral obligation because the question each citizen asks himself or should ask himself was not “What’s best for me?” Rather, each asks, “What’s best for all?” When all citizens ask this question and answer on the basis of what ought to be done, then, says Rousseau, they are expressing and following the general will. Enacting the general will is the only legitimately moral foundation for a law and the only expression of moral freedom. Getting men to ask this question and to answer it actively is the purpose of civic education.

Showing how to educate men to retain naturalness and yet to function in society and participate untouched by corruption in this direct democracy was the purpose of his educational treatise, Emile . If it could be done, Rousseau would show us the way. To do it would seem to require educating a man to be in society but not of society; that is, to be “attached to human society as little as possible” (Ibid, 105).

How could a man for Rousseau be a good man—meaning, for him a naturally good man (1979, 93), showing his amour de soi and also his natural compassion for others—and also have the proper frame of mind of a good citizen to be able to transcend self-interest and prescribe the general will? How could this be done in society when society’s influence is nothing but corrupting?

Rousseau himself seems ambivalent on exactly whether men can overcome social corruption. Society is based on private property; private property brings inequality, as some own more than others; such inequality brings forth social comparisons with others ( amour propre ), which in turn can produce envy, pride, and greed. Only when and if men can exercise their moral and political freedom and will the general will can they be saved from the corrupting influences of society. Willing for the general will, which is the good for all, is the act of a moral or good person. Its exercise in the assembly is the act of a good citizen.

Still, Rousseau comments that if “[f]orced to combat nature or the social institutions, one must choose between making a man or a citizen, for one cannot make both at the same time” (Ibid, 39). There seems little, if any, ambiguity here. One cannot make both a man and a citizen at the same time. Yet on the very next page of Emile Rousseau raises the question of whether a man who remains true to himself, to his nature, and is always decisive in his choices “is a man or a citizen, or how he goes about being both at the same time” (Ibid, 40).

Perhaps the contradiction might be resolved if we emphasize that a man cannot be made a man and a citizen at the same time, but he can be a man and a citizen at the same time. Rousseau hints at this distinction when he says of his educational scheme that it avoids the “two contrary ends…the contrary routes…these different impulses…[and] these necessarily opposed objects” (Ibid, 40, 41) when you raise a man “uniquely for himself.” What, then, will he be for others? He will be a man and a citizen, for the “double object we set for ourselves,” those contradictory objects, “could be joined in a single one by removing the contradictions of man…” (Idem). Doubtless, this will be a rare man, but raising a man to live a natural life can be done.

One might find the fully mature, and natural, Emile an abhorrent person. Although “good” in the sense of doing his duty and acting civilly, he seems nevertheless without imagination or deep curiosity about people or life itself—no interest in art or many books or intimate social relationships. Is his independence fear of dependence and thus built on an inability ever to be interdependent? Is he truly independent, or does he exhibit simply the appearance of independence, while the tutor “remains master of his person” (Ibid, 332)?

Whatever one thinks of Rousseau’s attempt to educate Emile—whether, for example, the tutor’s utter control of Emile’s life and environment is not in itself a betrayal of education—Rousseau is a precursor of those progressive educators who seek to permit children to learn at their own rate and from their own experiences, as we shall see below.

Mill argued that participation in representative government, or democracy, is undertaken both for its educative effects on participants and for the beneficial political outcomes. Even if elected or appointed officials can perform better than citizens, Mill thought it advisable for citizens to participate “as a means to their own mental education—a mode of strengthening their active faculties, exercising their judgment, and giving them a familiar knowledge of the subjects with which they are thus left to deal. This is a principal, though not the sole, recommendation of jury trial; of free and popular local and municipal institutions; of the conduct of industrial and philanthropic enterprises by voluntary associations” (1972, 179). Thus, political participation is a form of civic education good for men and for citizens.

On Liberty , the essay in which the above quotation appears, is not, writes Mill, the occasion for developing this idea as it relates to “parts of national education.” But in Mill’s view the development of the person can and should be undertaken in concert with an education for citizens. The “mental education” he describes is “in truth, the peculiar training of a citizen, the practical part of the political education of a free people, taking them out of the narrow circle of personal and family selfishness, and accustoming them to the comprehension of joint interests, the management of joint concerns—habituating them to act from public or semi-public motives, and guide their conduct by aims which unite instead of isolating them from one another” (Idem).

The occasion for discussing civic education as a method of both personal and political development is Mill’s Considerations on Representative Government . Mill wants to see persons “progress.” To achieve progress requires “the preservation of all kinds and amounts of good which already exist, and Progress as consisting in the increase of them.” Of what does Mill’s good consist? First are “the qualities in the citizens individually which conduce most to keep up the amount of good conduct…Everybody will agree that those qualities are industry, integrity, justice, and prudence” (1972, 201). Add to these “the particular attributes in human beings which seem to have a more especial reference to Progress…They are chiefly the qualities of mental activity, enterprise, and courage” (Ibid, 202).

So, progress is encouraged when society develops the qualities of citizens and persons. Mill tells us that good government depends on the qualities of the human beings that compose it. Men of virtuous character acting in and through justly administered institutions will stabilize and perpetuate the good society. Good persons will be good citizens, provided they have the requisite political institutions in which they can participate. Such participation—as on juries and parish offices—takes participants out of themselves and away from their selfish interests. If that does not occur, if persons regard only their “interests which are selfish,” then, concludes Mill, good government is impossible. “…[I]f the agents, or those who choose the agents, or those to whom the agents are responsible, or the lookers-on whose opinion ought to influence and check all these, are mere masses of ignorance, stupidity, and baleful prejudice, every operation of government will go wrong” (Ibid, 207).

For Mill good government is a two-way street: Good government depends on “the virtue and intelligence of the human beings composing the community”; while at the same time government can further “promote the virtue and intelligence of the people themselves” (Idem). A measure of the quality of any political institution is how far it tends “to foster in the members of the community the various desirable qualities…moral, intellectual, and active” (Ibid, 208). Good persons act politically as good citizens and are thereby maintained or extended in their goodness. “A government is to be judged by its actions upon men…by what it makes of the citizens, and what it does with them; its tendency to improve or deteriorate the people themselves.” Government helps people advance, acts for the improvement of the people, “is at once a great influence acting on the human mind….” Government is, then, “an agency of national education…” (Ibid, 210, 211).

Following Tocqueville, Mill saw political participation as the basis for this national education. “It is not sufficiently considered how little there is in most men’s ordinary life to give any largeness either to their conceptions or to their sentiments.” Their work is routine and dull; they proceed through life without much interest or energy. On the other hand, “if circumstances allow the amount of public duty assigned him to be considerable, it makes him an educated man” (Ibid, 233). In this way participation in democratic institutions “must make [persons] very different beings, in range of ideas and development of faculties, from those who have done nothing in their lives but drive a quill, or sell goods over a counter” (Idem).

There was no national public schooling in Mill’s Great Britain, and there were clearly lots of Britons without the requisite characteristics either of good citizens or of good men. Mill was certainly aware of this. He was much influenced by Tocqueville’s writings on the tyranny of the majority. Mill feared, as did Tocqueville, that the undereducated or uneducated would dominate and tyrannize politics so as to undermine authority and individuality. Being ignorant and inexperienced, the uneducated and undereducated would be susceptible to all manner of demagoguery and manipulation. So too much power in the hands of the inept and ignorant could damage good citizenship and dam the course of self-development. To remedy this Mill proposed two solutions: limit participation and provide the competent and educated with plural votes.

In Mill’s “ideally best polity” the highest levels of policymaking would be reserved for nationally elected representatives and for experts in the civil service. These representatives and experts would not only carry out their political duties, but they would also educate the public through debate and deliberation in representative assemblies, in public forums, and through the press. To assure that the best were elected and for the sake of rational government, Mill provided plural votes to those with college educations and to those of certain occupations and training. All citizens (but the criminal and illiterate) could vote, but not all citizens would vote equally. Some citizens, because they were educated or highly trained persons, were “better” than others: “…[T]hough every one ought to have a voice—that every one should have an equal voice is a totally different proposition…No one but a fool…feels offended by the acknowledgment that there are others whose opinion, and even whose wish, is entitled to a greater amount of consideration than his” (Ibid, 307–8).

But education was the great leveling factor. Though not his view when he wrote Considerations on Representative Government , Mill wrote in his autobiography that universal education could make plural voting unnecessary (1924, pp. 153, 183–84). Mill did acknowledge in Representative Government that a national system of education or “a trustworthy system of general examination” would simplify the means of ascertaining “mental superiority” of some persons over others. In their absence, a person’s years of schooling and nature of occupation would suffice to determine who would receive plural votes (1972, 308–09). Given Mill’s prescriptions for political participation and given the lessons learned from the deliberations and debates of representatives and experts, however, it is doubtful that civic education would have constituted much of his national education.

As noted above the founders of the United States tried to reduce the burdens on citizens, because they observed that republics had generally collapsed for lack of civic virtue. [ 4 ] However, they also created a structure that would demand more of citizens, and grant citizens more rights, than the empire from which they had declared independence. So virtually all of the founders advocated greater attention to civic education. When Alexander Hamilton wrote in Federalist 23 that the federal government ought to be granted “an unconfined authority in respect to all those objects which are entrusted to its management” (1987, p. 187), he underscored the need of the newly organized central government for, in Sheldon Wolin’s words, “a new type of citizen…one who would accept the attenuated relationship with power implied if voting and elections were to serve as the main link between citizens and those in power.” [ 5 ] Schools would be entrusted to develop this new type of citizen.

It is commonplace, therefore, to find among those who examine the interstices of democracy and education views much like Franklin Delano Roosevelt’s: “That the schools make worthy citizens is the most important responsibility placed on them.” In the United States public schools had the mission of educating the young for citizenship.

Initially education in America was not publicly funded. It wasn’t even a system, however inchoate. Instead it was every community for itself. Nor was it universal education. Education was restricted to free white males and, moreover, free white males who could afford the school fees. One of the “founders” of the public-school system in the United States, even though his era predated the establishment of public schools, was Noah Webster, who saw education as the tool for developing a national identity. As a result, he created his own speller and dictionary as a way of advancing a common American language.

Opposed to this idea of developing a national identity was Thomas Jefferson, who saw education as the means for safeguarding individual rights, especially against the intrusions of the state. Central to Jefferson’s democratic education were the “liberal arts.” These arts liberate men and women (though Jefferson was thinking only of men) from the grip of both tyrants and demagogues and enable those liberated to rule themselves. Through his ward system of education, Jefferson proposed establishing free schools to teach reading, writing, and arithmetic, and from these schools those of intellectual ability, regardless of background or economic status, would receive a college education paid for by the state.

When widespread free or publicly funded education did come to America in the 19 th century, it came in the form of Horace Mann’s “common school.” Such schools would educate all children together, “in common,” regardless of their background, religion, or social standing. Underneath such fine sentiments lurked an additional goal: to ensure that all children could flourish in America’s democratic system. The civic education curriculum was explicit, if not simplistic. To create good citizens and good persons required little beyond teaching the basic mechanics of government and imbuing students with loyalty to America and her democratic ideals. That involved large amounts of rote memorization of information about political and military history and about the workings of governmental bodies at the local, state, and federal levels. It also involved conformity to specific rules describing conduct inside and outside of school.

Through this kind of civic education, all children would be melded, if not melted, into an American citizen. A heavy emphasis on Protestantism at the expense of Catholicism was one example of such work. What some supporters might have called “assimilation” of foreigners into an American way of life, critics saw as “homogenization,” “normalization,” and “conformity,” if not “uniformity.” With over nine million immigrants coming to America between 1880 and the First World War, it is not surprising that there was resistance by many immigrant communities to what seemed insensitivity to foreign language and culture. Hence what developed was a system of religious—namely Catholic—education separate from the “public school” system.

While Webster and, after him, Mann wanted public education to generate the national identity that they thought democracy required, later educational reformers moved away from the idea of the common school and toward a differentiation of students. The Massachusetts Commission on Industrial and Technical Education, for example, pushed in 1906 for industrial and vocational education in the public schools. Educating all youth equally for participation in democracy by giving them a liberal, or academic, education, they argued, was a waste of time and resources. “School reformers insisted that the academic curriculum was not appropriate for all children, because most children—especially the children of immigrants and of African Americans—lacked the intellectual capacity to study subjects like algebra and chemistry” (Ravitch, 2001, 21).

Acting against this view of education was John Dewey. Because Dewey saw democracy as a way of life, he argued that all children deserved and required a democratic education. [ 6 ] As citizens came to share in the interests of others, which they would do in their schools, divisions of race, class, and ethnicity would be worn down and transcended. Dewey thought that the actual interests and experiences of students should be the basis of their education. I recur to a consideration of Dewey and civic education below.

2. The Good Democrat

Civic education can occur in all kinds of regimes, but it is especially important in democracies. In The Politics, Aristotle asks whether there is any case “in which the excellence of the good citizen and the excellence of the good man coincide” (1277a13–15). The answer for him is a politea or a mixed constitution in which persons must know both how to rule and how to obey. In such regimes, the excellence and virtues of the good man and the good citizen coincide. Democratic societies have an interest in preparing citizens to rule and to be ruled.

Modern democracies, however, are different from the ancient polis in several important and pertinent respects. They are mass societies in which most people can have little individual impact on government and policy. They are complex, technologically-driven, highly specialized societies in which professionals (including lawyers, civil servants, and politicians) have much more expertise than laypeople. And they are liberal constitutional regimes in which individual freedom is protected--to various degrees--and government is deliberately insulated from public pressure. For example, courts and central banks are protected from popular votes. Once the United States had become an industrialized mass society, the influential columnist Walter Lippmann argued that ordinary citizens had been eclipsed and could, at most, render occasional judgments about a government of experts (see The Phantom Public, 1925). John Dewey and the Chicago civic leader Jane Addams (in different ways) asserted that the lay public must and could regain its voice, but they struggled to explain how.

Several contemporary philosophers argue that citizens have a relatively demanding role and that they can and should be educated for it. Gutmann (1987), for example, argues that democratic society-at-large has a significant stake in the education of its children, for they will grow up to be democratic citizens. At the very least, then, society has the responsibility for educating all children for citizenship. Because democratic societies have this responsibility, we cannot leave the education of future citizens to the will or whim of parents. This central insight leads Gutmann to rule out certain exclusive suzerainties of power over educational theory and policy. Those suzerainties are of three sorts. First is “the family state” in which all children are educated into the sole good life identified and fortified by the state. Such education cultivates “a level of like-mindedness and camaraderie among citizens” that most persons find only in families (Ibid, 23). Only the state can be entrusted with the authority to mandate and carry out an education of such magnitude that all will learn to desire this one particular good life over all others.

Next is “the state of families” that rests on the impulse of families to perpetuate their values through their children. This state “places educational authority exclusively in the hands of parents, thereby permitting parents to predispose their children, through education, to choose a way of life consistent with their familial heritage” (Ibid, 28).

Finally, Gutmann argues against “the state of individuals,” which is based on a notion of liberal neutrality in which both parents and the state look to educational experts to make certain that no way of life is neglected nor discriminated against. The desire here is to avoid controversy, and to avoid teaching virtues, in a climate of social pluralism. Yet, as Gutmann points out, any educational policy is itself a choice that will shape our children’s character. Choosing to educate for freedom rather than for virtue is still insinuating an influential choice.

In light of these three theories that fail to provide an adequate foundation for educational authority, Gutmann proposes “a democratic state of education.” This state recognizes that educational authority must be shared among parents, citizens, and educational professionals, because each has a legitimate interest in each child and the child’s future. Whatever our aim of education, whatever kind of education these authorities argue for, it will not be, it cannot be, neutral. Needed is an educational aim that is inclusive. Gutmann settles on our inclusive commitment as democratic citizens to conscious social reproduction, the self-conscious shaping of the structures of society. To actuate this commitment we as a society “must educate all educable children to be capable of participating in collectively shaping their society” (Ibid, 14).

To shape the structures of society, to engage in conscious social reproduction, students will need to develop the capacities for examining and evaluating competing conceptions of the good life and the good society, and society must avoid the inculcation “in children [of the] uncritical acceptance of any particular way or ways of [personal and political] life” (Ibid, 44). This is the crux of Gutmann’s democratic education. For this reason, she argues forcefully that children must learn to exercise critical deliberation among good lives and, presumably, good societies. To assure that they can do so, limits must be set for when and where parents and the state can interfere. Guidelines must be introduced that limit the political authority of the state and the parental authority of families. One limit is nonrepression, which assures that neither the state nor any group within it can “restrict rational deliberation of competing conceptions of the good life and the good society” (Idem). In this way, adults cannot use their freedom to deliberate to prohibit the future deliberative freedom of children. Furthermore, claims Gutmann, nonrepression requires schools to support “the intellectual and emotional preconditions for democratic deliberation among future generations of citizens” (Ibid, 76.)

The second limit is nondiscrimination, which prevents the state or groups within the state from excluding anyone or any group from an education in deliberation. Thus, as Gutmann says, “all educable children must be educated” (Ibid, 45).

Gutmann’s point is not that the state has a greater interest than parents in the education of our children. Instead, her point is that all citizens of the state have a common interest in educating future citizens. Therefore, while parents should have a say in the education of their children, the state should have a say as well. Yet neither should have the final, or a monopolistic, say. Indeed, these two interested parties should also cede some of their educational authority to educational experts. There is, therefore, a collective interest in schooling, which is why Gutmann finds parental “choice” and voucher programs unacceptable.

But is conscious social reproduction the only aim of education? What about shaping one’s private concerns? Isn’t educating the young to be good persons also important? Or are the skills that encourage citizen participation also the skills necessary for making personal life choices and personal decision-making? For Gutmann, educating for one is also educating for the other: “…[M]any if not all of the capacities necessary for choice among good lives are also necessary for choice among good societies” (p. 40). She goes even further: “a good life and a good society for self-reflective people require (respectively) individual and collective freedom of choice” (Idem). Here Gutmann is stipulating that to have conscious social reproduction citizens must have the opportunity—the freedom and the capacities—to exercise personal or self-reflective choice.

Because the state is interested in the education of future citizens, all children must develop those capacities necessary for choice among good societies; this is simply what Gutmann means by being able to participate in conscious social reproduction. Yet such capacities also enable persons to scrutinize the ways of life that they have inherited. Thus, Gutmann concludes, it is illegitimate for any parent to impose a particular way of life on anyone else, even on his/her own child, for this would deprive the child of the capacities necessary for citizenship as well as for choosing a good life.

Gutmann’s position is that government can and must force one to participate in an education for citizenship. Children must be exposed to ways of life different from their parents’ and must embrace certain values such as mutual respect. On this last point Gutmann is insistent. She argues that choice is not meaningful, for anyone, unless persons choosing have “the intellectual skills necessary to evaluate ways of life different from that of their parents.” Without the teaching of such skills as a central component of education children will not be taught “mutual respect among persons” (Ibid, 30–31). “Teaching mutual respect is instrumental to assuring all children the freedom to choose in the future…[S]ocial diversity enriches our lives by expanding our understanding of differing ways of life. To reap the benefits of social diversity, children must be exposed to ways of life different from their parents and—in the course of their exposure—must embrace certain values, such as mutual respect among persons…” (Ibid, 32–33).

Yet what Gutmann suggests seems to go beyond seeing diversity as enrichment. She suggests that children not simply tolerate ways of life divergent from their own, but that they actually respect them. She is careful to say “mutual respect among persons,” which can only mean that neo-Nazis, while advocating an execrable way of life, must be respected as persons, though their way of life should be condemned. Perhaps this is a subtlety that Gutmann intended, but William Galston, for one, has come away thinking that Gutmann advocates forcing children to confront their own ways of life as they simultaneously show respect for neo-Nazis.

In our representative system, argues Galston, citizens need to develop “the capacity to evaluate the talents, character, and performance of public officials” (1989, p. 93). This, he says, is what our democratic system demands from citizens. Thus he disagrees with Gutmann, so much so that he says, “It is at best a partial truth to characterize the United States as a democracy in Gutmann’s sense” (Ibid, p. 94). We do not require deliberation among our citizens, says Galston, because “representative institutions replace direct self-government for many purposes” (Idem). Civic education, therefore, should not be about teaching the skills and virtues of deliberation, but, instead, about teaching “the virtues and competences needed to select representatives wisely, to relate to them appropriately, and to evaluate their performance in office soberly” (Idem).

Because civic education is limited in scope to what Galston outlines above, students will not be expected, and will not be taught, to evaluate their own ways of life. Persons must be able to lead the kinds of lives they find valuable, without fear that they will be coerced into believing or acting or thinking contrary to their values, including being led to question those ways of life that they have inherited. As Galston points out, “[c]ivic tolerance of deep differences is perfectly compatible with unswerving belief in the correctness of one’s own way of life” (Ibid, p. 99).

Some parents, for example, are not interested in having their children choose ways of life. Those parents believe that the way of life that they currently follow is not simply best for them but is best simpliciter . To introduce choice is simply to confuse the children and the issue. If you know the true way to live, is it best to let your children wade among diverse ways of life until they can possibly get it right? Or should you socialize the children into the right way of life as soon and as quickly as possible?

Yet what about the obligations that parents, as citizens, and children as future citizens, owe the state? How can children be prepared to participate in collectively shaping society if they have not received an education in how to deliberate about choices? To this some parents might respond that they are not interested in having their children focus on participation, or perhaps on anything secular. What these parents appreciate about liberal democracy is that there is a clear, and firm, separation between public and private, and they seek to focus exclusively on the private. Citizenship offers protections of the law, and it does not require participation. Liberal democracy certainly will not force one to participate.

Yet both Galston and Gutmann want to educate children for “democratic character.” Both see the need in this respect for critical thinking. For Galston children must develop “the capacity to evaluate the talents, character, and performance of public officials”; Gutmann seeks to educate the capacities necessary for choice among good lives and for choice among good societies. However much critical thinking plays in democratic character, active participation requires something more than mere skills, even thinking skills.

The concept of “social capital” was introduced by the sociologist James S. Coleman to refer to the value that is inherent in social networks (see, e.g., Coleman, 1988). The political scientist Robert Putnam subsequently argued that democracies function well in proportion to the strength of their social capital (1994) and that social capital is declining in the United States (2000). In his book Bowling Alone , Putnam explains, “Whereas physical capital refers to physical objects and human capital refers to properties of individuals [such as their own skills], social capital refers to connections among individuals—social networks and the norms of reciprocity and trustworthiness that arise from them. In that sense social capital is closely related to what some have called ‘civic virtue.’ The difference is that ‘social capital’ calls attention to the fact that civic virtue is most powerful when embedded in a dense network of reciprocal social relations” (Putnam 2000, p. 19).

A related idea is “collective efficacy,” as developed by the sociologist Robert Sampson and colleagues. It is the use--or ability to use--social networks to address common problems, such as crime. Sampson finds that the level of collective efficacy strongly predicts the quality of life in communities (Sampson, 2012).

If governments and communities function much better when people have social networks and use them for public purposes, then civic education becomes important and it is substantially about teaching people to create, appreciate, preserve, and use social networks. A pedagogical approach like Service Learning (see below) might be most promising for that purpose.

Elinor Ostrom won the 2009 Nobel Prize in Economic Sciences for her work on how people overcome collective action problems, such as the Prisoner’s Dilemma and the Tragedy of the Commons. These problems are endemic and serious, sometimes leading to environmental catastrophe and war. Ostrom, however, discovered many principles that allow people to overcome such problems. She wrote,

At any time that individuals may gain from the costly action of others, without themselves contributing time and effort, they face collective action dilemmas for which there are coping methods. When de Tocqueville discussed the ‘art and science of association,’ he was referring to the crafts learned by those who had solved ways of engaging in collective action to achieve a joint benefit. Some aspects of the science of association are both counterintuitive and counterintentional, and thus must be taught to each generation as part of the culture of a democratic citizenry. (Ostrom 1998)

Ostrom believed that these principles could be taught explicitly and formally, but the traditional and most effective means for teaching them were experiential. She argued that the tendency to centralize and professionalize management throughout the 20th century had deprived ordinary people of opportunities to learn from experience, and thus our capacity to address collective action problems had weakened.

Along with her husband Vincent Ostrom, Elinor Ostrom developed the idea of polycentric governance, according to which we are citizens of multiple, overlapping, and nested communities, from the smallest neighborhoods to the globe. Collective action problems are best addressed polycentrically, not reserved for national governments or parceled out neatly among levels of government. As president of the American Political Science Association and in other prominent roles, Ostrom advocated civic education that would teach people to address collective action problems in multiple settings and scales.

Deliberative democracy is the idea that a legitimate political decision is one that results from discussions among citizens under reasonably favorable conditions. Proponents debate precisely what qualifies as deliberation, but there is a general agreement that the discussion should be inclusive, free, equitable, and in some sense civil. In practical terms, deliberative democracy implies various efforts to increase the amount and the impact of public discussions. The philosophical underpinnings derive from the work of influential theorists including Jürgen Habermas, John Rawls, Michael Sandel, and others of varying views. See Gutmann and Thompson (1996) for an example of a sophisticated treatment that draws on many earlier works.

For civic education, the implication of deliberative democracy is that people should learn to participate in discussions, which may be both face-to-face and “mediated” by the news media and social media. Concretely, that means that people should develop the aptitude, desire, knowledge, and skills that lead them to read and discuss the news and current events with diverse fellow citizens and influence the government with the views that they develop and refine by deliberation. Practices such as discussing and debating current events in school seem especially promising.

Harry C. Boyte (1996, 2004) argues for the centrality of work to citizenship. We are not only citizens when we vote, read and discuss the news, and volunteer after school or work--which are all unpaid, voluntary activities. We are also citizens on the job; and even when we perform unpaid service, we should see our contributions as work-like in the sense that they are serious business. Citizens do not merely monitor and influence the government (per the theory of deliberative democracy) nor serve other people in community settings (emphasized in the idea of social capital); they also literally build, make, and maintain public goods. They do so whether they work in the public, private, or nonprofit sectors, for pay or not. Of course, they can work either well or badly, and a good citizen is one who makes valuable contributions to the public good, or builds “the commonwealth.”

The theory of public work suggests that civic education should be highly experiential and closely related to vocational education. Young people should gain skills and agency by actually making things together. A good outcome is an individual who will be able to contribute to the commonwealth through her or his work. Albert Dzur (2008), who holds a kindred but not identical view, emphasizes the importance of revising professional education so that professionals learn to collaborate better with laypeople.

3. The Good Person

The qualities of the good citizen are not simply the skills necessary to participate in the political system. They are also the virtues that will lead one to participate, to want to participate, to have a disposition to participate. This is what Rousseau was referring to when he described how citizens in his ideal polity would “fly to the assemblies” (1988, 140). Citizens, that is, ought to display a certain kind of disposition or character. As it turns out, and not surprisingly, given our perspective, in a democracy the virtues or traits that constitute good citizenship are also closely associated with being a good or moral person. We can summarize that close association as what we mean by the phrase “good character.”

It is the absence of these virtues or traits—that is, the absence of character—that leads some to conclude that democracy, especially in the United States, is in crisis. The withering of our democratic system, argues Richard Battistoni, for one, can be traced to “a crisis in civic education” and the failure of our educators to prepare citizens for democratic participation (1985, pp. 4–5). Missing, he argues, is a central character trait, a disposition to participate. Crucial to the continuation of our democracy “is the proper inculcation in the young of the character, skills, values, social practices, and ideals that foster democratic politics” (Ibid, p. 15); in other words, educating for democratic character.

Two groups predominate in advocating the use of character education as a way of improving democracy. One group comprises political theorists such as Galston, Battistoni, Benjamin Barber, and Adrian Oldfield who often reflect modern-day versions of civic republicanism. This group wishes to instill or nurture [ 7 ] a willingness among our future citizens to sacrifice their self-interests for the sake of the common good. Participation on this view is important both to stabilize society and to enhance each individual’s human flourishing through the promotion of our collective welfare.

The second group does not see democratic participation as the center, but instead sees democratic participation as one aspect of overall character education. Central to the mission of our public schools, on this view, is the establishing of character traits important both to individual conduct (being a good person) and to a thriving democracy (being a good citizen). The unannounced leader of the second group is educational practitioner Thomas Lickona, and it includes such others as William Bennett and Patricia White.

Neither group describes in actual terms what might be called “democratic character.” Though their work intimates such character, they talk more about character traits important to human growth and well-being, which also happen to be related to democratic participation. What traits do these pundits discuss, and what do they mean by “character”?

It is difficult, comments British philosopher R. S. Peters, “to decide what in general we mean when we speak of a person’s character as distinct from his nature, his temperament, and his personality” (1966, p. 40). Many advocates of character education are vague on just this distinction, and it might be helpful to propose that character consists of traits that are learned, while personality and temperament consist of traits that are innate. [ 8 ]

What advocates are clear on, however, is that character is the essence of what we are. The term comes from the world of engraving, from the Greek term kharakter , an instrument used for making distinctive marks. Thus character is what marks a person or persons as distinctive.

Character is not just one attribute or trait. It signifies the sum total of particular traits, the “sum of mental and moral qualities” ( O.E.D. , p. 163). The addition of “moral qualities” to the definition may be insignificant, for character carries with it a connotation of “good” traits. Thus character traits are associated, if not synonymous, with virtues. So a good person and, in the context of liberal democracy, a good citizen will have these virtues.

To Thomas Lickona a virtue is “a reliable inner disposition to respond to situations in a morally good way” (p. 51); “good character,” he continues, “consists of knowing the good, desiring the good, and doing the good” (Idem). Who determines what the good is? In general, inculcated traits or virtues or dispositions are used “in following rules of conduct.” These are the rules that reinforce social conventions and social order (Peters, p. 40). So in this view social convention determines what “good” means.

This might be problematic. What occurs when the set of virtues of the good person clashes with the set of virtues of the good citizen? What is thought to be good in one context, even when approved by society, is not necessarily what is thought to be good in another. Should the only child of a deceased farmer stay at home to care for his ailing mother, or should he, like a good citizen, join the resistance to fight an occupying army?

What do we do when the requirements of civic education call into question the values or beliefs of what one takes to be the values of being a good person? In Mozert v. Hawkins County Board of Education just such a case occurred. Should the Mozerts and other fundamentalist Christian parents have the right to opt their children out of those classes that required their children to read selections that went against or undermined their faith? On the one hand, if they are permitted to opt out, then without those children present the class is denied the diversity of opinion on the reading selections that would be educative and a hallmark of democracy. On the other hand, if the children cannot opt out, then they are denied the right to follow their faith as they think necessary. [ 9 ]

We can see, therefore, why educating for character has never been straightforward. William Bennett pushes for the virtues of patriotism, loyalty, and national pride; Amy Gutmann wants to see toleration of difference and mutual respect. Can a pacifist in a time of war be a patriot? Is the rebel a hero or simply a troublemaker? [ 10 ] Can idealized character types speak to all of our students and to the variegated contexts in which they will find themselves?

Should our teachers teach a prescribed morality, often closely linked to certain religious ideas and ideals? Should they teach a content only of secular values related to democratic character? Or should they teach a form of values clarification in which children’s moral positions are identified but not criticized?

These two approaches—a prescribed moral content or values clarification—appear to form the two ends of a character education spectrum. At one end is the method of indoctrination of prescribed values and virtues, regardless of sacred or secular orientation. But here some citizens will express concern about just whose values are to be taught or, to some, imposed. [ 11 ] At the same time, some will see the inculcation of specified values and virtues as little more than teaching a “morality of compliance” (Nord, 2001, 144).

At the other end of the spectrum is values clarification, [ 12 ] but this seems to be a kind of moral relativism where everything goes because nothing can be ruled out. In values clarification there is no right or wrong value to hold. Indeed, teachers are supposed to be value neutral so as to avoid imposing values on their students and to avoid damaging students’ self-esteem. William Damon calls this approach “anything-goes constructivism” (1996), for such a position may leave the door open for students to approve racism, violence, and “might makes right.”

Is there a middle of the spectrum that would not impose values or simply clarify values? There is no middle path that can cut a swath through imposition on one side and clarification on the other. Perhaps the closest we can get is to offer something like Gutmann’s or Galston’s teaching of critical thinking. Here students can think about and think through what different moral situations require of persons. With fascists looking for hiding Jews, I lie; about my wife’s new dress, I tell the truth (well, usually). Even critical thinking, however, requires students to be critical about something. That is, we must presuppose the existence, if not prior inculcation, of some values about which to be critical.

What we have, then, is not a spectrum but a sequence, a developmental sequence. Character education, from this perspective, begins with the inculcation in students of specific values. But at a later date character education switches to teaching and using the skills of critical thinking on the very values that have been inculcated.

This approach is in keeping with what William Damon, an expert on innovative education and on intellectual and moral development, has observed: “The capacity for constructive criticism is an essential requirement for civic engagement in a democratic society; but in the course of intellectual development, this capacity must build upon a prior sympathetic understanding of that which is being criticized” (2001, 135).

The process, therefore, would consist of two phases, two developmental phases. Phase One is the indoctrination phase. Yet which values do we inculcate? Perhaps the easiest way to begin is to focus first on those behaviors that all students must possess. In fact, without first insisting that students “behave,” it seems problematic whether students could ever learn to think critically. Every school, in order to conduct the business of education, reinforces certain values and behaviors. Teachers demand that students sit in their seats; raise their hands before speaking; hand assignments in on time; display sportsmanship on the athletic field; be punctual when coming to class; do not cheat on their tests or homework; refrain from attacking one another on the playground, in the hallways, or in the classroom; be respectful of and polite to their elders (e.g., teachers, staff, administrators, parents, visitors, police); and the like. The teachers’ commands, demands, manner of interacting with the students, and own conformity to the regulations of the classroom and school establish an ethos of behavior—a way of conducting oneself within that institution. From the ethos come the requisite virtues—honesty, cooperation, civility, respect, and so on. [ 13 ]

Another set of values to inculcate at this early stage is that associated with democracy. Here the lessons are more didactic than behavioral. One point of civic education in a democracy is to raise free and equal citizens who appreciate that they have both rights and responsibilities. Students need to learn that they have freedoms, such as those found in Bill of Rights (press, assembly, worship, and the like) in the U. S. Constitution. But they also need to learn that they have responsibilities to their fellow citizens and to their country. This requires teaching students to obey the law; not to interfere with the rights of others; and to honor their country, its principles, and its values. Schools must teach those traits or virtues that conduce to democratic character: cooperation, honesty, toleration, and respect.

So we inculcate in our students the values and virtues that our society honors as those that constitute good citizenship and good character. But if we inculcate a love of justice, say, is it the justice found in our laws or an ideal justice that underlies all laws? Obviously, this question will not arise in the minds of most, if any, first graders. As students mature and develop cognitively, however, such questions will arise. So a high-school student studying American History might well ask whether the Jim Crow laws found in the South were just laws simply because they were the law. Or were they only just laws until they were discovered through argument to be unjust? Or were they always unjust because they did not live up to some ideal conception of justice?

Then we could introduce Phase Two of character education: education in judgment. Judgment is based on weighing and considering reasons and evidence for and against propositions. Judgment is a virtue that relies upon practical wisdom; it is established as a habit through practice. Judgment, or thoughtfulness, was the master virtue for Aristotle from whose exercise comes an appreciation for those other virtues: honesty, cooperation, toleration, and respect.

Because young children have difficulty taking up multiple perspectives, as developmental psychologists tell us, thinking and deliberating that require the consideration of multiple perspectives would seem unsuitable for elementary-school children. Additionally, young children are far more reliant on the teacher’s involvement in presenting problem situations in which the children’s knowledge and skills can be applied and developed. R. S. Peters offers an important consideration in this regard:

The cardinal function of the teacher, in the early stages, is to get the pupil on the inside of the form of thought or awareness with which he is concerned. At a later stage, when the pupil has built into his mind both the concepts and the mode of exploration involved, the difference between teacher and taught is obviously only one of degree. For both are participating in the shared experience of exploring a common world (1966, 53).

The distinction between those moving into “the inside” of reflective thinking and those already there may seem so vast as to be a difference of kind, not degree. But the difference is always one of degree. Elementary-school students have yet to develop the skills and knowledge, or have yet to gain the experience, to participate in phase- two procedures that require perspectivism.

In this two-phased civic education teachers inculcate specific virtues such as patriotism. But at a later stage this orientation toward solidifying a conventional perspective gives way to one of critical thinking. The virtue of patriotism shifts from an indoctrinated feeling of exaltation for the nation, whatever its actions and motives, to a need to examine the nation’s principles and practices to see whether those practices are in harmony with those principles. The first requires loyalty; the second, judgment. We teach the first through pledges, salutes, and oaths; we teach the second through critical inquiry.

Have we introduced a significant problem when we teach students to judge values, standards, and beliefs critically? Could this approach lead to students’ contempt for authority and tradition? Students need to see and hear that disagreement does not necessarily entail disrespect. Thoughtful, decent people can disagree. To teach students that those who disagree with us in a complicated situation like abortion or affirmative action are wrong or irresponsible or weak is to treat them unfairly. It also conveys the message that we think that we are infallible and have nothing to learn from what others have to say. Such positions undercut democracy.

Would all parents approve of such a two-phased civic education? Would they abide their children’s possible questioning of their families’ values and religious views? Yet the response to such parental concerns must be the same as that to any authority figure: Why do you think that you are always right? Aren’t there times when parents can see that it is better to lie, maybe even to their children, than to tell the truth? This, however, presupposes that parents, or authority figures, are themselves willing to exercise critical judgment on their own positions, values, and behaviors. This point underscores the need to involve other social institutions and persons in character education.

4. Modern Forms of Civic Education

In the United States, most students are required to take courses on government or civics, and the main content is essentially political science for high school students. In other words, they use textbooks and other written materials to learn about the formal structure and behavior of political institutions, from local government to the United Nations (Godsay et al., 2012). The philosophical justifications for this kind of curriculum are rarely developed fully, but probably an underlying idea is that citizens ought to play certain concrete roles--voting, monitoring the news, serving on juries, petitioning the government--and to do so effectively requires a baseline understanding of the political system. Another implicit goal may be to increase young people’s appreciation of the existing constitutional system so that they will be motivated to preserve it.

Michael Rebell (2018) argues that both the United States Constitution and most states’ constitutional provisions regarding public education provide support for a right to adequate civic education . Specific policies should result from a deliberative process to define the educational opportunities that all students must receive and to select appropriate outcomes for civic education – all overseen by a court concerned with assessing whether civic education is constitutionally "adequate."

State standards are regulatory documents that affect the curriculum in public schools. All 50 states and the District of Columbia have adopted standards for civics as part of social studies (Godsay et al, 2012). The College, Career, and Civic Life ("C3") Framework for Social Studies State Standards (National Council for the Social Studies, 2013) provides a general framework for states to use as they design or revise these standards. It organizes civics – along with history, geography and economics – into one "Inquiry Arc" that extends from "Developing Questions and Planning Inquiries," to "Applying Disciplinary Concepts and Tools," to "Evaluating Sources and Evidence," to "Communicating Conclusions and Taking Informed Action." The Arc is presented as applicable from kindergarten through high school, but with increasingly demanding content. The logic of moving from question-generation to (ultimately) action suggests an implicit theory of civic engagement.

In the subsequent sections, we examine some proposals for alternative forms of civic education that are also philosophically interesting.

Putting students into the community-at-large is today called “service-learning.” It is a common form of civic education that integrates classroom instruction with work within the community. Ideally, the students take their experience and observations from service into their academic work, and use their academic research and discussions to inform their service.

Jerome Bruner, the renowned educator and psychologist, proposed that some classroom learning ought to be devoted to students creating political-action plans addressing significant social and political issues such as poverty or race. He also urged educators to get their students out into the local communities to explore the occupations, ways of life, and habits of residence. Bruner is here following Dewey, who criticized traditional education for its failure to get teachers and students out into the community to become intimately familiar with the physical, historical, occupational, and economic conditions that could then be used as educational resources (Dewey 1938, 40). Dewey warned of the “standing danger that the material of formal instruction will be merely the subject matter of the schools, isolated from the subject matter of life experience.” This could be countered by immersing students in “the spirit of service,” especially by learning about the various occupations within their communities (1916, 10–11, 49). [ 14 ]

Empirical evidence suggests that experiential education may be most effective for civic learning. “The reason, again, is that students respond to experiences that touch their emotions and senses of self in a firsthand way” (Damon, 2001, 141). Also, as Conover and Searing point out, “while most students identify themselves as citizens, their grasp of what it means to act as citizens is rudimentary and dominated by a focus on rights, thus creating a privately oriented, passive understanding” (2000, 108). To bring them out of this private and passive understanding, nothing is better, as Tocqueville noted, than political participation. The kind of participation here is political action, not simply voting or giving money. William Damon concludes that the most effective moral education programs “are those that engage students directly in action, with subsequent opportunities for reflection” (2001, 144).

Another influence on service-learning is the theory of social capital, described above. If a democracy depends on people serving one another and developing habits and networks of reciprocal concern--and if that kind of interaction is declining in a country like the United States--then it is natural to encourage or require students to serve as part of their learning.

Some critics (e.g., Boyte and Kari, 1996) worry that the “service” in “service-learning” reflects a narrow conception of citizenship that overlooks power and agency and that encourages an undemocratic distinction between the server and the served.

We can think of civic action as participation that involves far more than serving, voting, working or writing a letter to the editor. It can take many other forms: attending and participating in political meetings; organizing and running meetings, rallies, protests, fund drives; gathering signatures for bills, ballots, initiatives, recalls; serving on local elected and appointed boards; starting or participating in political clubs; deliberating with fellow citizens about social and political issues central to their lives; and pursuing careers that have public value.

The National Action Civics Collaborative (NACC) unites organizations that engage students in civic action as a form of civic learning. Service is usually only one form of “action.” Some NACC members work in schools, but similar practices are perhaps more common and easier to achieve in independent, community-based organizations. Youth Organizing is a widespread practice that engages adolescents in civic or political activities. Levinson (2012) offers a philosophically sophisticated defense of a pedagogy that she calls “guided experiential civic education” and argues for its place in public schools.

Especially if one’s theory of democracy is deliberative (see section 2.3, above ), the core of civic education may be learning to talk and listen with other people about public problems. That is a cognitively and ethically demanding activity that can be learned from experience. The most promising pedagogy is to discuss current events with a moderator--usually the teacher--and some requirement to prepare in advance.

Debates are competitive discussions. Simulations (such as mock trials or the Model UN) involve discussing issues from the perspective of fictional or historical characters. And deliberations usually involve students speaking in their own real voice and trying to find common ground.

Considerable evidence shows that moderated discussions of current, controversial issues increase students’ knowledge of civic processes, their skills at engaging with other people, and their interest in politics. See, e.g., Kawashima-Ginsberg and Levine (2014).

Hess (2009) and Hess & McAvoy (2014) argue for discussing current controversies and explore some of the ethical dilemmas that arise for teachers who do so. For instance, should a teacher disclose her or his own views or attempt to conceal them to be a neutral moderator? What questions should be presented as genuinely controversial? (Most people would insist that slavery is no longer a controversy and should not be treated as such. But what about the reality of climate change?)

John Dewey argued that, from the 18 th century onward, states came to see education as the best means of perpetuating and recovering their political power. But “the maintenance of a particular national sovereignty required subordination of individuals to the superior interests of the state both in military defense and in struggles for international supremacy in commerce…To form the citizen, not the ‘man,’ became the aim of education” (1916, 90).

In a democracy, however, because of its combination of “numerous and more varied points of shared common interest” and its requirement of “continuous readjustment through meeting the new situations produced by varied intercourse,” which Dewey called “progress,” education could address personal development and “full and free interplay” among social groups (Ibid, 83, 79). In other words, it is in democratic states that we want to look for the preparation of good persons as well as good citizens; that is, for democratic education, which in this context, to repeat for emphasis, is what is meant by civic education.

Nowhere is there a better site for political or democratic action than the school itself, the students’ own community. This is Dewey’s insight (1916). Creating a democratic culture within the schools not only facilitates preparing students for democratic participation in the political system, but it also fosters a democratic environment that shapes the relationships with adults and among peers that the students already engage in. “Students learn much more from the way a school is run,” comments Theodore Sizer, “and the best way to teach values is when the school is a living example of the values to be taught” (1984, 120, 122).

Real problems, and not hypotheticals or academic exercises, are, Dewey argued, always of real concern to students. So in addition to activities of writing and classroom discussion, typical of today’s public schools, students should engage in “active inquiry and careful deliberation in the significant and vital problems” that confront their communities, however defined but especially their schools (1910, 55). Book lessons and classroom discussions rarely connect with decision-making on issues that affect that community. In fact, Dewey comments that traditional methods of instruction are often “foreign to the existing capacities of the young…beyond the reach of [their] experience…[T]he very situation forbids much active participation by pupils” (1938, 19).

As a core of learning Dewey wanted “an experiential continuum” (1938, 28, 33). The experiences that he wanted to promote were those that underscored healthy growth; those, in other words, that generated a greater desire to learn and to keep on learning and that built upon prior experiences. “[D]emocratic social experiences” were superior in providing “a better quality of human experience” than any other form of social or political organization (Ibid, 34).

One logical, and practical, possibility was to make the operations of the school part of the curriculum. Let the students use their in-school experiences to make, or help make, decisions that directly affect some of the day-to-day operations of the school—student discipline, maintenance of the grounds and buildings, problems with cliques, issues of sexism and racism, incidents of ostracism, and the like—as well as topics and issues inside the classrooms.

Dewey thought of schools as “embryo communities” (1915, 174), “institution[s] in which the child is, for the time…to be a member of a community life in which he feels that he participates, and to which he contributes” (1916, 88). We need not become sidetracked in questioning just what Dewey means by, or what we should mean by, “community” to grasp the sense that he is after. It is not surprising that Dewey wanted to give students experience in making decisions that affect their lives in schools. What is surprising is that so little democracy takes place in schools and that those who spend the most time in schools have the least opportunity to experience it.

The significance of democratic decision-making within the schools and about the wider community—the making of actual decisions through democratic means—cannot be overstated. As a propaedeutic to democratic participation, political action of this sort is invaluable. Melissa S. Williams comments: “…[L]earning cooperation as a practice is the only way to develop individuals’ sense of agency to reshape the world they share with others. It teaches moderation in promoting one’s own vision, and the capacity of individuals to see themselves as part of a project of collective self-rule” (2005, 238; emphasis in original).

Of course, not everything in school should be decided democratically. There are some areas in which decisions require expertise—a combination of experience and knowledge—that rules out students as decision-makers. Chief among such areas is pedagogy. Because the teachers and administrators know more about the processes of education and about their subjects, because they have firsthand and often intimate knowledge of the range and nature of abilities and problems of their students—a point emphasized by Dewey (1938, 56)—as well as the particular circumstances in which the learning takes place, they and not the students should make pedagogical decisions.

At the same time, because many students are still children, the decisions that they are to make should be age-appropriate. Not all democratic procedures or school issues are suitable for all ages. Differences in cognitive, social, and emotional development, especially at the elementary-school level, complicate democratic action. While all students may have the same capacity as potentiality, activating those capacities requires development, as noted in the discussion of a two-phased form of civic education.

Deweyan ideas about the school as a community live on in several kinds of practice. First, in some experimental schools, students, teachers, and parents actually govern democratically. In a Sudbury School (of which the first was founded in Sudbury, Massachusetts in 1968), the whole community governs the institution through weekly town meetings.

Much more common is to give students some degree of voice in the governance of a school through an elected student government, student-run media, and policies that encourage students to express their opinions.

Another very prevalent approach is to support and encourage students to manage their own voluntary associations within a school: clubs, teams, etc. Thomas & McFarland (2010) and others have found positive affects of extracurricular participation on voting, and a plausible explanation is that adolescents become active citizens by managing their own mini-communities.

In his critique of traditional pedagogy, Paulo Freire refers to teacher-centered education as the “banking concept of education” (1970, 72). This for Freire is unacceptable as civic education. Too often, observes Freire, students are asked to memorize and repeat ideas, stanzas, phrases, and formulas without understanding the meaning of or meaning behind them. This process “turns [students] into ‘containers,’ into ‘receptacles’ to be ‘filled’ by the teacher” (Idem). As a result, students are nothing but objects, nothing but receptacles to receive, file, and store deposits—that is, containers for what the teacher has deposited in their “banks.”

Like Dewey, Freire thinks that knowledge comes only from invention and reinvention and the perpetual inquiry in the world that is a mark of all free human beings. Students thereby educate the teachers as well. In sharp contrast, then, to the banking concept is “‘problem-posing’ education” (Ibid, 79), which is an experiential education that empowers students by educing the power that they already possess.

That power is to be used to liberate themselves from oppression. This pedagogy to end oppression, as Freire writes, “must be forged with , not for , the oppressed” (1970, 48; emphases in original), irrespective of whether they are children or adults. Freire worked primarily with illiterate adult peasants in South America, but his work has applications as well to schools and school-aged children. It is to be a pedagogy for all, and Freire includes oppressors and the oppressed.

To overcome oppression people must first critically recognize its causes. One cause is people’s own internalization of the oppressor consciousness [or “image,” as Freire says at one point (Ibid, 61)]. Until the oppressed seek to remove this internalized oppressor, they cannot be free. They will continue to live in the duality of both oppressed and oppressor. It is no wonder, then, as Freire tells us, that peasants once promoted to overseers become more tyrannical toward their former workmates than the owners themselves (Ibid, 46). The banking concept of education precludes the perspective that students need to recognize their oppression: “The more students [or adults] work at storing the deposits entrusted to them, the less they develop the critical consciousness which would result from their intervention in the world as transformers of that world” (Ibid, 73).

Having confronted the reality of the dual nature of her consciousness, having discovered her own internal oppressor and realized her actual situation, the person now must act on her realization. She must act, in other words, in and on the world so as to lessen oppression. Freire wanted his students, whether adult peasants or a country’s youth, to value their cultures as they simultaneously questioned some of those cultures’ practices and ethos. This Freire referred to as “reading the word”—as in ending illiteracy—and “reading the world”—the ability to analyze social and political situations that influenced and especially limited people’s life chances. For Freire, to question was not enough; people must act as well.

Liberation, therefore, is a “praxis,” but it cannot consist of action alone, which Freire calls “activism.” It must be, instead, action combined with “serious reflection” (Ibid, 79, 65). This reflection or “reflective participation” takes place in dialogue with others who are in the same position of realization and action.

This “critical and liberating dialogue,” also known as “culture circles,” is the heart of Freire’s pedagogy. The circles consist of somewhere between 12 and 25 students and some teachers, all involved in dialogic exchange. The role of the “teachers” in this civic education is to participate with the people/students in these dialogues. “The correct method for a revolutionary leadership…is, therefore, not ‘libertarian propaganda.’ Nor can the leadership merely ‘implant’ in the oppressed a belief in freedom…The correct method lies in dialogue” (Ibid, 67).

The oppressed thereby use their own experiences and language to explain and surmount their oppression. They do not rely upon others, even teachers, to explain their oppressed circumstances. “Through dialogue, the teacher-of-the-students and the students-of the-teacher cease to exist and a new term emerges: teacher-student with students-teachers” (Ibid, 80). The reciprocity of roles means that students teach teachers as teachers teach students. Dialogue encourages everyone to teach and everyone to create together.

Because Freire worked with illiterate adult peasants, he insisted that the circles use the ways of speaking and the shared understandings of the peasants themselves. In the circles the learners identify their own problems and concerns and seek answers to them in the group dialogue. Dialogue focuses on what Freire called “codifications,” which are representations of the learner’s day-to-day circumstances (Ibid, 114 and passim). Codifications may be photographs, drawings, poems, even a single word. As representations, codifications abstract the daily circumstances. For example, a photograph of workers in a sugar cane field permits workers to talk about the realities of their work and working conditions without identifying them as the actual workers in the photograph. This permits the dialogue to steer toward understanding the nature of the participants’ specific circumstances but from a more abstract position. Teachers and learners worked together to understand the problems identified by the peasants, a process that Freire calls “decoding,” and to propose actions to be taken to rectify or overturn those problems.

The circles therefore have four basic elements: 1) problem posing, 2) critical dialogue, 3) solution posing, and 4) plan of action. The goal, of course, is to overcome the problems, but it is also to raise the awareness, the critical consciousness (conscientization), of the learners so as to end oppression in their individual and collective lives. The increased critical awareness enables learners to appropriate language without being colonized by it. [ 15 ] Decoding allows participants “to perceive reality differently…by broadening the horizon of perception…[It] stimulates the appearance of a new perception” that allows for the transformation of the participants’ concrete reality (Ibid 115).

“Finally,” comments Freire, “true dialogue cannot exist unless the dialoguers engage in critical thinking…thinking which perceives reality as process, as transformation, rather than as a static activity” (Ibid, 92).

True dialogue is for Freire what civic education must be about. If civic education does not include it, then there is little hope that the future will be anything for the oppressed but a continuation of the present. “Authentic education is not carried on by ‘A’ for ‘B’ or by ‘A’ about ‘B,’ but by ‘A’ with ‘B’…” (Ibid, 93; emphases in original). Essential to such education are the experiences of the students, whatever their ages or situations. Naively conceived humanism, part and parcel of so much traditional education, tries “to create an ideal model of the ‘good man,’” but does so by leaving out “the concrete, existential, present situation of real people” (Idem). Therefore, traditional civic education, non-experiential civic education that overlooks the importance of Freire’s praxis, fails for Freire to raise either good persons or good citizens.

The Brazilian government has recognized Freire’s culture circles as a form of civic education and has underwritten their use for combating illiteracy among youth and adults (Souto-Manning, 2007).

Cosmopolitanism is an emerging and, because of globalization, an increasingly important topic for civic educators. In an earlier iteration, cosmopolitan education was multicultural education. According to both, good persons need to be aware of the perspectives of others and the effects their decisions have on others. While multicultural good citizens needed to think about the perspectives and plight of those living on the margins of their societies and about those whose good lives deviated from their own, good citizens in cosmopolitanism need to think, or begin to think, of themselves as “global citizens” with obligations that extend across national boundaries. Should and must civic education incorporate a global awareness and foster a cosmopolitan sensibility?

Martha Nussbaum, for one, thinks so. Nussbaum argues that our first obligation must be to all persons, regardless of race, creed, class, or border. She does not mean that we ought to forsake our commitments to our family, friends, neighbors, and fellow citizens. She means that we ought to do nothing in our other communities or in our lives that we know to be immoral from the perspective of Kant’s community of all humanity (1996, 7). We should “work to make all human beings part of our community of dialogue and concern” (Ibid, 9). Civic education should reflect that (Ibid, 11).

Philosopher Eamonn Callan, however, thinks otherwise. Callan wants to avoid a civic education, and the pursuit of justice that underlies it, “that gives pride of place to a cosmopolitan sensibility at the cost of particularistic affiliations” (1999, p. 197). In Callan’s view our civic education should be constructed ideally around the concept of “liberal patriotism.” Although liberal patriotism is an “identification with a particular, historically located project of political self-rule”—that is, American liberal democracy—it nevertheless also “entails a sense of responsibility to outsiders and insiders alike….” (Ibid, 198).

Of course, the danger here is that a liberal patriot may well feel a sense of obligation or responsibility only when her country is committing the injustice. Callan points out that it is “precisely the thought that ‘we Americans’ have done these terrible things that gave impetus [during the Vietnam war] to their horror and rage” (Idem). This thought is to be contrasted with our feelings and sense of responsibility when, as Callan suggests, Soviet tanks rolled through Prague. Because, according to Callan, our politico-moral identity was not implicated in the Soviet action, we somehow do not have to have a similar sense of horror and rage. Perhaps we do not have to, but should we? Nussbaum’s point is that we certainly should.

What, therefore, should civic education look like? Callan provides two examples: Should we “cultivate a civic identity in which patriotic affinities are muted or disappear altogether and a cosmopolitan ideal of ‘world citizenship’ is brought” to the forefront? Or should we cultivate a kind of patriotism “in which identification with a particular project of democratic self-rule is yet attuned to the claims of justice that both civic outsiders and insiders” will make (1999, 198). It appears that Nussbaum would favor the first, while Callan favors the second.

Perhaps these two are not the only options. In her metaphor of concentric identity circles Nussbaum argues that we ought to try to bring the outer circles of our relationships, the circle of all humanity, closer to the center, to our selves and to our loved ones (1996, 9). By doing so, we do not push out of our identities those particular relationships of significance to us. Instead, we need to take into consideration the effects that our moral and political decisions have on all of humanity. If our civic education helps us extend our sympathies, as Hume proposed, and if we could do so without paying the price of muting or eliminating our local and national affinities, then would Nussbaum and Callan agree on such a civic education?

Additionally, we need to consider that patriotism itself seems to have its own version of concentric circles. For example, Theodore Roosevelt warned against “that overexaltation of the little community at the expense of the great nation.” Here is a nod toward Roosevelt’s “New Nationalism” as opposed to what he called “the patriotism of the village.” [ 16 ] If we move from the village to the nation, then can’t we move from the nation to the world? As Alexander Pope wrote in “An Essay on Man”: “God loves from Whole to Parts; but human soul/Must rise from Individual to the Whole/…Friend, parent, neighbor first it will embrace/His country next, and next all human race.”

Is it ever too early to begin educating children about the cultures, customs, values, ideas, and beliefs of people from around the world? Will this undercut our commitment and even devotion to our own family, neighborhood, region, and nation? No civic education must consist exclusively either of love of one’s community and a patriotic affiliation with one’s country or of preparation for world citizenship—a term that implies, at the least, a world state. There ought to be a composite that will work here.

If the purpose of civic education is to generate in the young those values that underscore successful participation in our liberal democracies, then the task facing educators, whether in elementary school, secondary school, or post-secondary school, might be far easier than we imagine. There seems to be a direct correlation between years in school and an increase in tolerance of difference (Nie et al., 1996). An increase of tolerance can lead to an increase of respect for those holding divergent views. Such increases could certainly help engender a cosmopolitan sensibility. But does the number of years in school correlate with a willingness to participate in the first place? For example, the number of Americans going to college has increased dramatically over the past 50 years, yet voting in elections and political participation in general are still woefully low.

Perhaps public schools should not teach any virtue that is unrelated to the attainment of academic skills, which to some is the paramount, if not the sole, purpose of schooling. But shouldn’t all students learn not just the skills but also the predispositions required to participate in the “conscious social reproduction” of our democracies, as Gutmann argues? If our democracies are important and robust, then do our citizens need such predispositions to see the value of participation? And if we say that our democracies are not robust enough, then shouldn’t our students be striving to reinvigorate, or invigorate, our democratic systems? Will they need infusions of patriotism to do that? If tolerance and respect are democratic virtues, then do we fail our students when we do not tolerate or respect their desires as good persons to eschew civic participation even though this violates what we think of as the duties of good citizens?

As stated earlier, civic education in a democracy must prepare citizens to participate in and thereby perpetuate the system; at the same time, it must prepare them to challenge what they see as inequities and injustices within that system. Yet a civic education that encourages students to challenge the nature and scope of our democracies runs the risk of turning off our students and turning them away from participation. But if that civic education has offered more than simply critique, if its basis is critical thinking, which involves developing a tolerance of, if not an appreciation for, difference and divergence, as well as a willingness and even eagerness for political action, then galvanized citizens can make our systems more robust. Greater demands on our citizens, like higher expectations of our students, often lead to stronger performances. As Mill reminds us, “if circumstances allow the amount of public duty assigned him to be considerable, it makes him an educated man” (Ibid, 233).

  • Aristotle. The Politics , Stephen Everson (ed.), New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988.
  • Battistoni, Richard M., 1985. Public Schooling and the Education of Democratic Citizens , Jackson: University Press of Mississippi.
  • –––, 1993. The Book of Virtues: A Treasury of Moral Stories , New York: Simon & Schuster.
  • Boyte, Harry C., 2004. Everyday Politics , Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
  • –––, and Nancy N. Kari, 1996. Building America: The Democratic Promise of Public Work , Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
  • Bruner, Jerome, 1961. The Process of Education , New York: Vintage Books/Random House.
  • –––, 1917. “The Process of Education Revisited,” Phi Delta Kappan , 52 (1): 18–21.
  • Callan, Eamonn, 1999. “A Note on Patriotism and Utopianism,” Studies in Philosophy and Education , 18: 197–201.
  • Conover, P.J. and Searing, D. D., 2000. “A Political Socialization Perspective,” in L.M. McDonnell, P. M. Timpane, and R. Benjamin (eds.), Rediscovering the Democratic Purposes of Education , Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas, 91–124.
  • Delli Carpini, M. X. and Keeter, S., 1996. Citizen Competence and Democratic Institutions , University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania University Press.
  • Damon, William, 2001. “To Not Fade Away: Restoring Civic Identity Among the Young,” in Diane Ravitch and Joseph P. Viteritti (eds.), Making Good Citizens. New Haven: Yale University Press, 122–141.
  • –––, 1996. Greater Expectations , New York: Free Press.
  • Dewey, John, 2004 [1916]. Democracy and Education , Mineola, NY: Dover Publications.
  • –––, 1991/[1910]. How We Think , New York: Prometheus Books.
  • –––, 1976/[1938]. Experience and Education , New York: Collier/Macmillan.
  • Dewey, John and Dewey, Evelyn, 1915 . Schools of Tomorrow , New York: E. P. Dutton.
  • Dzur, Albert W., 2008. Democratic Professionalism: Citizen Participation and the Reconstruction of Professional Ethics, Identity, and Practice , University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.
  • Freire, Paulo, 2006/[1970]. Pedagogy of the Oppressed , New York: Continuum.
  • Galston, William, 2001. “Political Knowledge, Political Engagement, and Civic Education,” Annual Review of Political Science , 4: 217–234.
  • –––, 1989. “Civic Education in the Liberal State,” in Nancy Rosenblum (ed.), Liberalism and the Moral Life , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 89–102.
  • Godsay, Surbhi, Whitney Henderson, Peter Levine, and Josh Littenberg-Tobias, 2012. State Civic Education Requirements , Medford, MA: CIRCLE (Center for Information and Research on Civic Learning and Engagement).
  • Gutmann, A., 1987, Democratic Education , Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
  • –––, and Dennis Thompson, 1996. Democracy and Disagreement , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Hess, Diana, 2009. Controversy in the Classroom: The Democratic Power of Discusssion , New York: Routledge
  • Hess, Diana & McAvoy, Paula, 2014. The Political Classroom: Evidence and Ethics in Democratic Education , New York: Routledge.
  • Kant, Immanuel, 1970. Kant’s Political Writings , Reiss, Hans (ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • KawashimaGinsberg, Kei and Peter Levine, 2014. “Diversity in Classrooms: The Relationship between Deliberative and Associative Opportunities in School and Later Electoral Engagement,” Analyses of Social Issues and Public Policy , 14(1): 394–414.
  • Levinson, Meira, 2012. No Citizen Left Behind , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Lickona, Thomas, 1991. Educating for Character , New York: Bantam.
  • Locke, John, 1693, Some Thoughts Concerning Education , London: A. and J. Churchill.
  • Locke, John, 1703, “Some Thoughts Concerning Reading and Education for a Gentleman,” in John Locke, Political Essays , Mark Goldie (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1997, 348–358.
  • –––, “Instructions for the conduct of a young Gentleman, as to religion and government,” from 1714 correspondence with R. King, published in J. Locke, Some Thoughts Concerning Education, with Introduction and Notes by the Rev. R. H. Quick , M.A. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1889, p. 192.
  • Macedo, Stephen, 2000. Diversity and Distrust: Civic Education in a Multicultural Society , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Madison, James, 1788. “Remarks to the Virginia ratifying convention on June 20, 1788,” The Papers of James Madison , edited by William T. Hutchinson, et al., Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1977, Vol. 11, p. 163.
  • –––, and Alexander Hamilton, and John Jay, 1788. The Federalist Papers , I. Kramnick (ed.), New York: Penguin Books, 1987.
  • Mill, John Stuart, 1924. Autobiography , New York: Columbia University Press.
  • –––, 1972. Utilitarianism, On Liberty and Considerations on Representative Government , London: Everyman’s Library/Dent.
  • Mozert v. Hawkins County Board of Education , 1987. 827 F. 2 nd 1062 (6 th Circuit).
  • National Council for the Social Studies, 2013. College, Career, and Civic Life (‘C3’) Framework for Social Studies State Standards , available online .
  • Nie, Norman, et al ., 1996. Education and Democratic Citizenship in America , Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Niemi, Richard G. and Junn, Jane, 1998. Civic Education: What Makes Students Learn , New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • Nord, Warren A., 2001. “Moral Disagreement, Moral Education, and Common Ground,” in D. Ravitch and J.P. Viteritti (eds.), Making Good Citizens: Education and Civil Society , New Haven: Yale University Press, 142–167.
  • Nussbaum, Martha C., 1996. “Cosmopolitanism and Patriotism,” in J. Cohen (ed.), For Love of Country , Boston: Beacon Press, 3–17.
  • Oldfield, Adrian, 1990. Citizenship and Community , New York: Routledge.
  • Peters, R. S., 1966. Ethics and Education , London: Allen & Unwin.
  • Plato, “The Laws,” The Complete Works of Plato , T.J. Saunders (trans.), John Cooper (ed.), Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co., 1997.
  • Putnam, Robert D., 1994. Making Democracy Work: Civic Traditions in Modern Italy , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Putnam, Robert D., 1995. “Bowling Alone,” Journal of Democracy , 6: 65–78.
  • –––, 2000, Bowling Alone: The Collapse and Revival of American Community , New York: Simon & Shuster
  • Ravitch, Diane, 2001. “Education and Democracy,” in Making Good Citizens , Diane Ravitch and Joseph P. Viteritti (Eds ). New Haven: Yale University Press, 15–29.
  • Ravitch, Diane and Joseph P. Viteritti (eds.), 2001. Making Good Citizens: Education and Civil Society , New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • Rebell, Michael A., 2018. Flunking Democracy: Schools, Courts, and Civic Participation , Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 1988. The Social Contract , Maurice Cranston (trans.), New York: Viking Penguin.
  • –––, 1979. Emile or On Education , Allan Bloom (trans.), New York: Basic Books.
  • Sherrod, Lonnie R., Constance Flanagan, and James Youniss, 2002. “Dimensions of Citizenship and Opportunities for Youth Development: The What, Why, When, Where, and Who of Citizenship Development,” Applied Developmental Science , 6(4): 267.
  • Souto-Manning, Mariana, 2006. “Education for Democracy,” in E. Doyle Stevick and Bradley A. U. Levinson (eds.), Reimagining Civic Education , Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield, 121–146.
  • Thomas, Reuben and Daniel McFarland, 2010. “Joining Young, Voting Young: The Effects of Youth Voluntary Associations on Early Adult Voting,” Medford, MA: Center for Information and Research on Civic Lerarning and Engagement.
  • Williams, Melissa S., 2005. “Citizenship and Functions of Multicultural Education,” in K. McDonough and W. Feinberg (eds.), Citizenship and Education in Liberal-Democratic States: Teaching for Cosmopolitan Values and Collective Identities , New York: Oxford University Press, 208–47.
  • Wolin, Sheldon, 1989. The Presence of the Past: Essays on the State and the Constitution , Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
  • Avery, P.G., 1994. “The Future of Political Participation in Civic Education,” in The Future of the Social Studies , Social Science Education Consortium, 47–52.
  • Barber, Benjamin, 1992. An Aristocracy of Everyone: the Politics of Education and the Future of America , New York: Ballantine Books.
  • Battistich, V., and D. Solomon and M. Watson, & Schaps, E., 1997. “Caring School Communities,” Educational Psychologist , 32: 137–151.
  • Battistoni, R. M., 2002. Civic Engagement Across the Curriculum , Providence, RI: Campus Compact.
  • Bennett, William, The Book of Virtues , New York: Simon & Schuster, 1993.
  • Benninga, Jacques, 1991. Moral, Character, and Civic Education in the Elementary School , New York: Teacher College Press.
  • Butts, R. Freeman, 1989. The Civic Mission in Educational Reform , Stanford, CA: Hoover Institution Press.
  • Callan, Eamonn, 1997. Creating Citizens: Political Education and Liberal Democracy , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Camino, L., & S. Zeldin, 2002. “From Periphery to Center: Pathways for Youth Civic Engagement in the Day-to-Day Life of Communities,” Applied Developmental Science , 6 (4): 213–220.
  • Coby, Barbara, 2003. Building Partnerships for Service Learning , San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
  • Coleman, James S. (1988) “Social Capital in the Creation of Human Capital,” American Journal of Sociology , 94 (Supplement): S95–120.
  • Dudley, R.L., and A.R. Gitelson, 2002. “Political Literacy, Civic Education, and Civic Engagement: A Return to Political Socialization?” Applied Developmental Science , 6 (4): 175–182.
  • Eyre, Linda and Richard, 1993. Teaching Your Children Values , New York: Simon & Schuster.
  • Galston, W.A., 2001. “Political Knowledge, Political Engagement, and Civic Education,” Annual Review of Political Science , 4: 217–234.
  • Issacs, David, 1984. Character Building: A Guide for Parents and Teachers , Dublin: Four Courts Press.
  • Jaeger, Werner, 1945. Paideia: The Ideals of Greek Culture , 3 volumes, Gilbert Highet (trans.), New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Kilpatrick, William, 1992. Why Johnny Can’t Tell Right from Wrong , New York: Simon & Schuster.
  • Lickona, Thomas, 1983. Raising Good Children , New York: Bantam Books.
  • Lisman, C. D., 1998. Toward a Civil Society: Civic Literacy and Service Learning , Westport, CT: Bergin & Garvey.
  • McDonnell, L.M., and P.M. Timpane, and R. Benjamin (eds.), 2000. Rediscovering the Democratic Purposes of Education , Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas.
  • Nucci, Larry, 1989. Moral Development and Character Education: A Dialogue , Berkeley: McCuthan.
  • Ostrom, Elinor. 1998. “The Need for Civic Education: A Collective Action Perspective,” Workshop in Political Theory and Policy Analysis, Indiana University, Bloomington, IN Workshop Working Paper W98–26.
  • Rahn, W.M., & J.E. Transue, 1998. “Social Trust and Value Change: The Decline of Social Capital in American Youth, 1976–1995,” Political Psychology , 19: 545–565.
  • Rebell, Michael A., 2018. Flunking Democracy: Schools, Courts, and Civic Participation , Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2018.
  • Sampson, Robert J., 2012. Great American City: Chicago and the Enduring Neighborhood Effect , Chicago: University of Chicago Press
  • Torney-Purta, J., 2002. “The School’s Role in Developing Civic Engagement: A Study of Adolescents in Twenty-eight Countries,” Applied Developmental Science , 6 (4): 203–212.
  • Walker, T., 2002. “Service and Political Participation: What Research Tells Us,” Applied Developmental Science , 6 (4): 183–188.
  • White, Patricia, 1996. Civic Virtues and Public Schooling: Educating Citizens for a Democratic Society , New York: Teachers College Press.
  • Wynne, Edward and Kevin Ryan, 1993. Reclaiming Our Schools: A Handbook on Teaching Character, Academics and Discipline , New York: Macmillan.
  • Youniss, J., and M. Yates, 1999. “Youth Service and Moral-Civic Identity: A Case for Everyday Morality,” Educational Psychology Review , 11 (4): 363 – 378.
  • Zukin, Cliff, and Scott Keeter, Molly Andolina, Krista Jenkins, and Michael X. Delli Carpini, 2006. A New Engagement? Political Participation, Civic Life, and the Changing American Citizen , New York: Oxford University Press.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.
  • Center for Civic Education , home of the educational programs “We the People” and “Project Citizen.” Traditionally funded by the federal government and thus interesting as an expression of official policies toward civic education
  • CIRCLE or the Center for Information and Research on Civic Learning and Engagement , based in Tufts University’s Jonathan M. Tisch College of Citizenship and Public Service, this center promotes research and projects on civic and political engagement of the young.
  • Close Up Foundation , which runs a Washington DC experiential learning program for middle-school and high-school students.
  • Constitutional Rights Foundation , which focuses on educating America’s youth about the importance of democratic participation.
  • Sabo Center for Democracy and Citizenship , affiliated with Augsburg University and engaged in activist democracy through projects involving public work.
  • Public Achievement , a civic engagement initiative that seeks to involve the young in learning lessons of democracy by doing public work.

character, moral | citizenship | cosmopolitanism | democracy | Dewey, John | ethics: virtue | Mill, John Stuart | Rousseau, Jean Jacques

Copyright © 2018 by Jack Crittenden Peter Levine < Peter . Levine @ tufts . edu >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2024 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

Center for Civic Education brand mark

Center Staff

State Network

  • State Programs At-a-Glance

Board & Councils

  • Board of Directors
  • National Advisory Council

History of the Center

Annual Reports

We the People

  • About the Program
  • How to Use We the People
  • Curriculum by Grade Level
  • Simulated Hearings
  • National & State Competitions
  • 2024 National Finals
  • 2024 National Invitational
  • Professional Learning
  • Supplemental Resources
  • Level 3 Resources
  • Level 2 Resources
  • Level 1 Resources
  • Program Impact
  • State Competitions
  • 2023 National Finals
  • 2023 National Invitational
  • Hearing Questions
  • Scoring Rubric Videos
  • Resource Center Level 3
  • Resource Center Level 2
  • Resource Center Level 1

Project Citizen

  • National Showcases
  • Curriculum In Focus

Civitas International

  • About the Toolkit
  • How-To Use the Toolkit
  • Principles of the Constitution
  • Evolution of Political Parties
  • Women's Rights
  • Civil Rights in America
  • Citizenship
  • Civics Empowers All Students
  • James Madison Legacy Project Expansion
  • Project Citizen Research Program

Teacher Resources

  • Self-Paced Courses
  • The Constitution EXPLAINED Videos
  • Constitution Day
  • Bill of Rights
  • Voting and Elections
  • 60-Second Civics
  • Quotations about Democracy

Civics Inquiry Lesson Plans

  • Lower Voting Age
  • Who Are We the People?
  • Escaping Misinformation
  • Has Dr. King's Legacy Been Fulfilled?

EAD Crosswalks

  • We the People Level 1
  • We the People Level 2
  • We the People Level 3

Learn.Civiced.org

  • We the People Open Course
  • Strengthening Democracy Open Course

For Teachers

Resource Materials

  • Civics Renewal Network
  • Civics Teacher Corps
  • EAD Champion
  • WTP Alumni Network
  • Ways to Give

Image

Sign Up Today for the Smarter Way to Stay On Top of Civic Education

Image

Pre-Order the New Project Citizen Level 2 Textbook and Teacher's Guide, Featuring Media-Literacy Content

Image

The 2024-25 We the People High School State Hearing Questions Have Been Announced! Download Them Now

Image

Mark Your Calendars for a Four-Part Documentary Featuring We the People Students

National finals, portland's grant high school places first in the center's nationwide competition on the constitution, check out our 60-second civics daily podcast and quiz, discover the center's impact with our fy2023 annual report, our mission at work.

We provide free and low-cost civic education

We Provide Affordable Civic Education

We the People students

We Enable Effective Citizenship

Civics students

We Advance Civic Knowledge

​please give to support civic education, sign up for civics news.

We the People

Center for Civic Education

5115 Douglas Fir Road, Suite J Calabasas, CA 91302

  Phone: (818) 591-9321

  Email: [email protected]

  Media Inquiries: [email protected]

  Website: www.civiced.org

  • Our Programs
  • Our Networks

logo

Log in or create a new account:

civic education

Welcome to Learn.civiced.org!

Learn about american constitutional government.

This site is for educators and lifelong learners. Click a button below to watch scholars in our open course, participate in our discussion forum, and explore a variety of learning resources.

Open Courses

Free, self-paced We the People and Strengthening Democracy in America courses to deepen understanding of the U.S. Constitution and the American political system.

Instructor-led Courses

Participate in structured courses with esteemed scholars and facilitators to expand your learning  and grow professionally.

Civics Forum

Discuss civics and government content and share instructional ideas in this online community for educators.

Featuring free ebooks, links to lesson plans, primary sources, and many other great resources for teaching and learning about civics and government.

Innovate Education

Inform policy, inspire engagement, illustrate impact, see our impact, impact stories, annual reports, our history, our founder, get involved:, communities, for the future of u.s., looking for our free educational resources, something special happens when we have confidence in our democracy..

We engage. We raise a hand. We lift our voices. We listen to each other.

We come together to share ideas and solve common challenges.

And every time we do, our nation gets stronger.

We put more faith, trust, and belief in one another. We spark a more virtuous cycle toward a future we can all believe in.

That’s the promise of our nation. And it starts here .

Learn About Our Strategic Vision

Students interacting with computer game showing electoral map

We empower educators with resources that build the knowledge, skills, and dispositions students need for informed civic participation.

Capital building

We advance policy at the state and national levels to make civic education a priority for the health and strength of our nation.

in the midst of students raising hands

We invite and engage a diverse network of learners and leaders in the movement for high-quality civic education.

students walking out of school doors

We evaluate and share evidence-based findings that demonstrate the value and impact of civic education for our country’s future.

The impact we make together

95 percent of teachers icon

Illustrating the impact we make, lorem ipsum sitamet consecttuer adipsc

Saturnino Pajkos

Read more from Satu

Student/Youth Fellow

Shari teacher desk

High School Teacher

Michael Martirone

High School Social Studies Teacher

Inspiring a passion for civic learning so young people can shape the world around them and believe in our country’s future

Connect with iCivics at upcoming events and conferences…

Political Science’s Role in the Roadmap to Educating for American Democracy

Political Science’s Role in the Roadmap to Educating for American Democracy

What's in Store for 2024 with Shawn P. Healy, Ph.D.

What's in Store for 2024 with Shawn P. Healy, Ph.D.

Sandra Day O’Connor

iCivics Founder and Former U.S. Supreme Court Justice

News and Insights

civic education

New Collection of Resources Teaches Students How to Verify Online Information

Civic Digital Literacy, developed by the Digital Inquiry Group and iCivics, is a collection of nonpartisan, evidence-based resources to help middle and high school students learn how to navigate misinformation, disinformation, and AI-generated content.

Brief the Chief title card

iCivics and the White House Historical Association Launch “Brief the Chief,” a New Digital Game Showing Students How Presidents Throughout History Relied on Multiple Perspectives to Make Difficult Choices

Developed in consultation with top historians and educational games experts, Brief the Chief gives students insight into American history by teaching them how Thomas Jefferson, Abraham Lincoln, and Lyndon B. Johnson navigated complicated governing situations.

civic education

New Research Provides K-12 Civic Education Insights

Released at the Civic Learning Week National Forum in Washington, D.C., new research shows the need to provide more robust civic learning opportunities in high school, the positive effects of students openly discussing civic and political issues, the effect of legislation on teachers and students, and the need for more civic role models.

Invest in iCivics Today

iCivics works to ensure high-quality civic education opportunities are available for every student in the United States, preparing them for informed engagement in our nation’s self-governing society.

With your support, that vision is within our reach. Today, up to 145,000 teachers and 9 million students in all 50 states utilize iCivics’ innovative and free resources. Your tax-deductible donation helps us further our reach and deepen our impact, ensuring the practice of democracy is learned and embraced by each new generation.

A portrait of civics education in the United States: The 2018 Brown Center Report

Subscribe to the brown center on education policy newsletter, louis serino ls louis serino communications manager, governance studies - the brookings institution, managing editor - brown center chalkboard.

June 27, 2018

American schools found themselves immersed in politics this year. A wave of anti-gun violence demonstrations swept the nation following the shooting at Marjory Stoneman Douglas High School, controversial federal policies aroused fear and concern for undocumented students, and teacher rallies and strikes flared up across the country. This occurred amid broader unrest and polarization, with many Americans expressing concern about the state of our politics and the cohesiveness of our society.

In this environment, are U.S. schools equipping students with the tools to become engaged, informed, and empathetic citizens? Are they equipping some students—or groups of students—better than others?

The 2018 Brown Center Report on American Education endeavors to answer these questions, and others, with three separate analyses of issues related to civics education. Chapter 1 analyzes trends in students’ civics scores (as well as math and reading) on the National Assessment of Education Progress (NAEP); Chapter 2 examines state policy related to civics education; and Chapter 3 provides a look at the nation’s social studies teachers. Read on for highlights of the report.

Trends in NAEP math, reading, and civics scores

The first chapter explores trends in student performance on NAEP assessments from the late 1990s through the most recent year in which results are available: 2014 in civics, 2017 for math and reading. Math scores climbed sharply in No Child Left Behind’s (NCLB’s) early years, but scores have largely plateaued since then. Scores follow this pattern in fourth-grade reading, but eighth-grade reading scores show slight gains recently after remaining flat initially.

Despite social studies not featuring prominently in NCLB testing requirements, scores on NAEP civics assessments have remained steady or climbed slightly. However, analysis shows that there are wide and persistent gaps by race, ethnicity, and income in civics. As of 2014, the white-black gap was 0.83 standard deviations (SD), the income gap (based on free and reduced-price lunch eligibility) was 0.82 SD, and the white-Hispanic gap was 0.71 SD. These gaps equate to multiple years of academic learning.

NAEP test score gaps-civics, grade 8

“The size of these gaps is disconcerting,” the authors write. “Civic participation affords political power, and broad participation is essential for a healthy, inclusive democracy.” Recent U.S. education policy has focused narrowly on student performance in core academic subjects, specifically math and reading. However, the Every Student Succeeds Act, which replaced NCLB in 2015, has the potential to change that, granting greater flexibility to states in designing their accountability systems.

Read Chapter 1 in full here.

A 50-state inventory of state civics requirements

In the second chapter , the authors analyze the extent to which states have incorporated recommended practices into requirements for civics education, compiling an inventory that spans all 50 states and Washington, D.C. After review, 42 states plus Washington, D.C., require at least one course related to civics education as a high school graduation requirement; most states require two or three. However, only about half have incorporated participatory elements of learning or community engagement, such as mock trials, into their standards. While discussion and knowledge-building components of civics education appear frequently across states, participatory elements and community engagement appear less common.

In addition, the authors look at survey data to investigate whether student experiences reflect these practices. About 63 percent of 12th-grade students report discussing current events on at least a weekly basis. But only 24 percent report taking part in debates or panel discussions on a weekly basis, while 31 percent report never participating in this type of activity. This is a concern, the authors write, “given the sentiment among civics education experts that a high-quality civics education is incomplete without teaching students what civic participation looks like in practice and how citizens can engage in their communities.”

12th-grade students reported participation in civics-oriented activities

Read Chapter 2 in full here.

Understanding the social studies teacher workforce

The final chapter of the 2018 Brown Center Report focuses on the state of America’s social studies teachers. By presenting statistics on the demographics, qualifications, responsibilities, compensation, and satisfaction of high-school social studies teachers, the authors reveal how these educators differ from other subject-specialized teachers.

Synthesizing existing research with original analysis of nationally representative survey data, the authors make several discoveries about the nature of American social studies teachers. Well over half—58 percent—of social studies teachers are male, compared to 41 percent of natural science teachers, 38 percent of math teachers, and 20 percent of English language arts (ELA) teachers. They also take on responsibilities outside of the classroom more often, including coaching. In fact, 35 percent report having coaching responsibilities, versus 23 percent of natural science teachers, 21 percent of math teachers, and 15 percent of ELA teachers. “These patterns suggest schools may often be looking for candidates that can fill multiple roles beyond the classroom when hiring social studies teachers, which seems less the case for vacancies in other subjects.”

Gender breakdown of teachers by subject

Despite several differences, social studies teachers are similar to other teachers on a number of dimensions, including teachers’ age and experience levels, course load, working hours, and satisfaction with their school. Therefore, it is important not to overstate these disparities to truly understand America’s social studies educators. The authors conclude, “By understanding the teaching force we have in social studies and comparing it with the teaching force we might need, we can better answer questions about which policies and practices would strengthen the social studies teacher workforce.”

Read Chapter 3 in full here.

The full report

These chapters provide a portrait of how complex and varied civics education is in the United States, using student performance, state policies, teacher characteristics, and survey results as windows into students’ experiences. Overall, the 2018 Brown Center Report argues that education policy and practice in the United States should place greater emphasis on schools’ role in supporting and strengthening American democracy.

Read the full report here.

K-12 Education

Governance Studies

Brown Center on Education Policy

Lydia Wilbard

August 29, 2024

Zachary Billot, Annie Vong, Nicole Dias Del Valle, Emily Markovich Morris

August 26, 2024

Brian A. Jacob, Cristina Stanojevich

The Civic Life

You are here: american university the civic life.

Students gather on the quad to relax and talk

Back to top

A university-wide initiative for civic education and engagement.

Civics is the cornerstone of human interaction. How we engage with one another, with communities, and with institutions, shapes politics, economics and business, education, and culture. Civics done well is constructive, collaborative, and additive. A critical part of building a campus climate of respect and belonging and preparing our students to be leaders in a complex world is fostering the knowledge and skills of civic engagement. How we engage matters.

We all need to learn and practice the skills of persuasion based on research, evidence, ethical reasoning, intellectual humility, teamwork, resilience, active listening, and respect. Together we will learn how to approach these conversations with the understanding that we will not always agree, but we can find paths forward together.

The Civic Life builds on American University’s strengths in civic education and engagement across numerous disciplines (ranging from politics to the arts to STEM to business) and provides the tools we all need to engage and solve problems with one another and across viewpoints, perspectives, and lived experiences. While we often talk about civics in terms of democracy, elections, and government, it is a much broader concept that is at the heart of who we are and what we do.

The Civic Life brings together curricular and co-curricular opportunities, classroom discussions, perspectives from both AU and external experts, partnerships with leading organizations such as Institute for Citizens and Scholars, community service opportunities, and numerous other ways for community members to interact, learn, and grow. It will feature signature AU centers and programs, such as the Sine Institute of Policy and Politics, the Project on Civic Dialogue, AU Votes, and the Polarization and Extremism Research and Innovation Lab (PERIL), among others. This includes a Dialogues Across Differences initiative to advance our inclusive excellence work and key values of respectful inquiry, critical thinking, and active listening. 

Programs & Events

Students work on a laptop covered in AU stickers

Here's how to  check your state's deadline  if you're mailing an absentee ballot,  register to vote in Washington, DC , and more!

A faculty member and student engage in conversation

Project on Civic Dialogue

Founded in 2018, the project helps students cultivate a love of and the skills for listening and communicating ideas across differences.

Student asking question at event

Dialogue Across Differences

This new initiative will promote and model AU’s key values of respectful inquiry, critical thinking, active listening, and principled changemaking. 

Event: Dialogue across Differences Kickoff

Dialogue Across Differences

Wednesday, August 28 4:00-6:00PM Friedham Quad

Join the Office of Inclusive Excellence for food and fun as we kick off the year by celebrating AU's commitment to dialogue across differences. Meet fellow students, faculty, and staff from across campus and learn how to get involved.  Learn More

Ultimately, the program will educate our community to be informed and engaged members of society, promote dialogue, and build connections. An understanding of civics helps individuals understand their rights and responsibilities as citizens, promotes critical thinking and problem-solving, and contributes to responsible action. By engaging in this work, every AU student can achieve learning outcomes that lead to both individual opportunities and success and broader progress in our society.  

Fixing the Foundation: Civics Education Reform To Solve America’s Youth Voting Crisis

Civic Nation

  • Share to Facebook
  • Share to Twitter
  • Share to Linkedin

Record youth voter turnout in 2018 and 2020 came amidst waves of heightened enthusiasm around those elections. National get-out-the-vote campaigns channeled that energy to successfully mobilize millions of young voters. But in the post-pandemic world, election excitement plummeted, revealing systemic barriers to voting that impacted the rates at which young people (18-29 year olds) were able to exercise their vote. And now, as enthusiasm appears to be making a comeback, we have a unique opportunity to address those barriers in a way that keeps the enthusiasm of the past month going far into the future.

In my organizing experience as Co-Chair of the Harvard Votes Challenge , I’ve seen how quickly youth engagement — not just in the election, but with US democracy at large — has plummeted in recent years, and my observations closely align with the national picture. The most recent Harvard Youth Poll found that only 9% of young Americans aged 18-29 believe the country is “generally headed in the right direction,” over two-thirds are more fearful than hopeful about our country’s future, and institutional trust has plummeted to all-time lows. Bursts of enthusiasm may obscure this crisis of faith, but they do not fix it. We cannot continue to rely on those bursts to sustain youth voter turnout in the long run.

And as my peers became less engaged, I noticed that many of them suffer from a lack of election preparation as well. They weren’t taught how to research issues. They weren’t taught how to request absentee ballots. They weren’t even taught how to register to vote! The problem is pervasive.

Student organizers with the Harvard Votes Challenge celebrating a successful semester of student voter mobilization.

We’re now facing a dual crisis of civic engagement among young people in America: a crippling shortfall of confidence in our democracy coupled with a total lack of procedural knowledge for how to participate in that democratic system. Even when young Americans are excited about a specific campaign or election, these barriers still hold them back. In the face of such a crisis, a surprisingly simple solution emerges: fixing high school civics education.

Civics education in high school is foundational in encouraging democratic engagement for the rest of one’s life. If done correctly, it provides practical preparation for voting and helps form values of civic responsibility, addressing both parts of the aforementioned crisis. But, as it stands today, high school civics education has failed to meet the moment.

Polling from last fall shows just how underprepared young Americans are for civic participation coming out of high school. Just around half of young people were taught in high school to appreciate the importance of their vote, but even more strikingly, only a quarter of young people were prepared for all four of the following key procedural aspects of voting: how to register to vote, knowing voting deadlines, how to research candidates and issues, and how to request and submit ballots. Across the board, very few members of Gen Z have entered adulthood ready to exercise their civic duty in practice. The consistency of these trends across demographic divides suggests a systemic flaw in civics education.

Teaching students the importance of their vote goes hand in hand with teaching them the process of voting itself. Data overwhelmingly suggests that those who are more engaged and informed about politics are far more likely to vote and are more hopeful about democracy at large. And those who were prepared to vote in high school are twice as likely to be politically engaged!

It all starts in the classroom. High school is the one time where almost everyone goes through a system capable of teaching them the fundamentals of how to be an engaged citizen. However, civic education at present tends to emphasize traditional fact-based knowledge and test preparation over participatory instruction . While learning about political debates in early American history can absolutely help inform why our democracy works the way it does, such lessons do very little to convince high school students that they should go out and vote in this century. That has to change.

Ariana Singh, founder of youth voter registration organization Generation Z Votes, presenting to an auditorium of high school students in Texas. Organizations like this aim to fill the gap left by inadequate civics education curriculum.

Will implementing participatory civics instruction into the high school curriculum be a cure-all for our voting woes? Of course not. There are a whole host of barriers facing young voters that have to be overcome beyond insufficient high school civics education, from navigating restrictive ID laws and busy schedules to researching policy platforms and finding motivation to vote. But it’s a great start. Improving high school civics education is a critical step in the right direction because it would remove one of the most significant barriers to voting and lend momentum to a growing culture of democratic responsibility among American youth.

And now — as young voters are excitedly tuning into the election — is the perfect time to take this step. Immediately after President Biden announced he was not running for reelection, there was a massive spike in youth political enthusiasm. As memes of coconut trees and references to being “unburdened by what has been” have swept across the internet, negativity has given way to hope, optimism, and energy on a level that hasn’t been seen in quite some time.

We must capitalize on the momentum of the 2024 election cycle to institutionalize civic engagement on a whole new level. The disengagement of the past few years revealed the structural barriers facing young voters. All of the newfound excitement around the election means we can finally confront those barriers head-on. This is a unique opportunity to strengthen the foundation of our democracy, rekindle faith in our political system, and revitalize young Americans’ hope for the future.

In the long run, we cannot solve the issue of youth disengagement unless we address the root cause. Young Americans need a reason to care. They need greater representation, and institutions need to regain their trust. Until then, we’ll keep treading water; but reforming civics education should get the ball rolling. It’ll make more years of record youth turnout possible, and speaking selfishly, it’ll make my job as a college voter organizer a little easier. Give young people the tools to make their voices heard at the ballot box and I guarantee you they will put those tools to good use.

Students, parents, teachers, administrators, curriculum designers, and community members can all play a role. It takes a village to raise a voter. So ask yourself: what can you do in your community to help students become engaged citizens for the rest of their lives? Take the first step today and encourage everyone you know to make a plan to vote: allin.vote/plan .

More than 1045 colleges and universities currently participate in the ALL IN Campus Democracy Challenge, including Harvard University. Learn more about ALL IN and support our work here .

Jordan Schwartz

  • Editorial Standards
  • Reprints & Permissions

Civics For Life

BOOST YOUR CIVICS IQ

Whether you never had civics in school or simply want to brush up, Civics 101 is here for you!

Civics 101 is a free, online comprehensive compilation of easy, accessible micro-lessons designed to provide every American citizen with the civic knowledge and skills necessary for active participation in our democracy.

Click Here to Learn More About Civics 101

civic education

Our new, free, online resource answers questions about and helps Americans navigate the presidential primaries.

______________________, click here to learn more.

civic education

The new series, Elections and How They Work , covers topics such as the rights and responsibilities of voting, and more.

___________________________________

Click Here to Browse Micro-Lessons

civic education

New Evidence on Trickle-Down and Trickle-Up Influences in Civic Education and Engagement  uses K-12, birth, and voting records for over 580,000 students to compile descriptive evidence on how trickle-down and trickle-up socialization influences civic engagement.

Click here to read the full policy brief , welcome to civics for life, civics is the study of the rights and duties of citizenship. civics for life is our multigenerational online resource center for civics education, civil discourse and civic engagement. our free, online lifelong learning platform fills the civics knowledge gap for countless americans. .

civic education

Public Square | Electoral College

Voter ballot.

November 2024 General Election: How Are Secretaries of State Preparing Nationwide?

civic education

Citizens Guide to the General Election 2024

Civics 101 logo

Civics 101: Micro-Lessons for Multigenerational Learners

civic education

Youth Civics Education Programs

civic education

Talking Revolution, with Nathan Perl-Rosenthal

Join our online community and be your best citizen..

How We Can Repair Our Democracy and Build a More Perfect Union

US House Convenes After Failing To Elect Speaker

A merica’s civic education crisis is not new, but it is becoming increasingly dire. New data released by the Department of Education—known as the Nation’s Report Card and widely regarded as the best assessment of how well we are educating our future citizens—paints a stark and worrying picture. Eighth graders scored worse on the history section this year than in in any year since the test was first administered on the subject in 1994, and civics scores dropped for the first time since it was first tested in 1998, with less than one in every four students scoring proficient.

The political polarization that poisons our politics is only deepening this crisis. When our political leaders wage “ school wars ” over what historical models can and cannot be taught in the classroom, they signal to students that certain views are simply not worth considering. When our media promote the loudest and most antagonistic voices, students learn that shouting is more effective than listening. And when parents refuse to engage arguments with which they disagree, students come to believe that listening to opposing viewpoints is a sign of weakness rather than civic strength. Small wonder, then, that according to one recent UCLA-UC Riverside study , more than two-thirds of high school principals reported substantial political conflict over hot-button issues inside their classrooms.

If we fail to teach our children the principles of our democracy and the habits of civil dialogue necessary to sustaining it, we will endanger the American project. Instead of building a better future by finding common ground, they will only slide deeper into partisanship and extremism.

Read More: Parents Should Have a Voice in Their Kids’ Education, But We’ve Gone Too Far

Fortunately, there is a way out, but it requires a new way of thinking about civic education. To solve this educational crisis, we need to teach students not just history and civics, but the virtues of democratic citizenship, beginning with the ability to consider arguments with which we disagree and to engage in dialogue and deliberation with people with views different from our own. In practice, this means giving students a rigorously non-partisan education in American history and civics, including exposing them to the best arguments on all sides of the major constitutional debates past and present and giving them the tools to make up their own minds.

At the founding, leading framers including George Washington and James Madison dreamed of a national university that would bring together young Americans of different perspectives and backgrounds to teach the habits of deliberation and the core civic knowledge necessary to informed citizenship. They never built this institution, but technology makes it possible for us to do so today.

For example, our organizations are partnering to create a free online Constitution 101 course premised on a simple, radical act: bringing together genuine experts who genuinely disagree about the most important constitutional issues facing our nation today and using their examples to model thoughtful, respectful civil dialogue. With a “faculty” composed of leading conservative and liberal historians, constitutional scholars, judges, and public servants, our course will teach students America’s constitutional principles using primary sources spanning American history, including Supreme Court decisions and the dissents. By being exposed to ideas across the ideological spectrum, students will have the content and the space to consider America’s past and present from multiple perspectives and then reach their own conclusions.

There is already evidence that this approach works. In research conducted during a pilot phase of this new course, we found that 20% of students reported an increased desire to engage in difficult conversations both inside and outside their classrooms.

Of course, this new educational model cannot work alone. Members of Congress and the media, among others, need to commit to having civil dialogue with their ideological opponents. It will take all the adults in the room to show our young citizens that compromise and deliberation are not vestiges of their grandparents’ America.

As we approach America’s 250th birthday in 2026, we have the opportunity to reverse our civics spiral and revitalize knowledge of the ideals, rooted in the Declaration of Independence and the Constitution, that unite us. It will be up to all of us—students and parents, teachers and senators—to rise to the challenge.

More Must-Reads from TIME

  • Breaking Down the 2024 Election Calendar
  • How Nayib Bukele’s ‘Iron Fist’ Has Transformed El Salvador
  • What if Ultra-Processed Foods Aren’t as Bad as You Think?
  • How Ukraine Beat Russia in the Battle of the Black Sea
  • Long COVID Looks Different in Kids
  • How Project 2025 Would Jeopardize Americans’ Health
  • What a $129 Frying Pan Says About America’s Eating Habits
  • The 32 Most Anticipated Books of Fall 2024

Contact us at [email protected]

  • Student Voices

Nov. 3, 2020, 2:53 p.m.

Why civics education is necessary

civic education

Civic education, when done right, can uplift and empower students. It can help us find our voices and use them effectively.

civic education

Recent Student Voicess

<bound method CaptionedImage.default_alt_text of <CaptionedImage: Aftermath of shooting at Oxford High School in Michigan>>

Where students stand on gun violence ahead of 2024 election

Hear from students on how they'd like to address gun violence and whether or not parents should be held legally responsible for actions of their children

<bound method CaptionedImage.default_alt_text of <CaptionedImage: 20240401_190257 (1)>>

Student Voice: How I became an inventor (and how you can, too)

Hear from a student inventor about her path to invention, and why she thinks any student can do the same

<bound method CaptionedImage.default_alt_text of <CaptionedImage: Screen Shot 2024-05-24 at 4.49.17 PM>>

Student Voice: A young inventor's "Farmer's Friend" makes farming safer

Student inventor Maia De La Cruz explains her invention to make moving hay easier for farmers

<bound method CaptionedImage.default_alt_text of <CaptionedImage: Screen Shot 2024-05-29 at 10.27.32 AM>>

Student Movie Recommendation: 'Bridge of Spies' finds a connection between the two sides of the Cold War

Hear from one high school student about why a movie set in during the Cold War is relevant today

  • student-voice
  • civic engagement
  • volunteering
  • #NationalVoterRegistrationDay
  • Super Civics
  • civic participation
  • 2020 presidential election

SUPPORTED BY VIEWERS LIKE YOU. ADDITIONAL SUPPORT PROVIDED BY:

<bound method CaptionedImage.default_alt_text of <CaptionedImage: lemelson_logo-2447736847_360>>

Copyright © 2023 NewsHour Production LLC. All Rights Reserved

Illustrations by Annamaria Ward

Home

  • University News
  • Faculty & Research
  • Health & Medicine
  • Science & Technology
  • Social Sciences
  • Humanities & Arts
  • Students & Alumni
  • Arts & Culture
  • Sports & Athletics
  • The Professions
  • International
  • New England Guide

The Magazine

  • Current Issue
  • Past Issues

Class Notes & Obituaries

  • Browse Class Notes
  • Browse Obituaries

Collections

  • Commencement
  • The Context

Harvard Squared

  • Harvard in the Headlines

Support Harvard Magazine

  • Why We Need Your Support
  • How We Are Funded
  • Ways to Support the Magazine
  • Special Gifts
  • Behind the Scenes

Classifieds

  • Vacation Rentals & Travel
  • Real Estate
  • Products & Services
  • Harvard Authors’ Bookshelf
  • Education & Enrichment Resource
  • Ad Prices & Information
  • Place An Ad

Follow Harvard Magazine:

University News | 3.1.2021

A Roadmap for Reforming Civic Education

A u.s. department of education-funded study, coauthored by danielle allen, calls for urgent reinvestment in civic education..

Photographs of the U.S. Capitol, the White House, and the Supreme Court, representing the three branches of government.

Among the findings of a new survey on civic knowledge is that barely half of American adults can name all three branches of government. Montage by Niko Yaitanes/ Harvard Magazine ; images by Unsplash. 

Several months before the invasion of the United States Capitol threw the nation’s seat of legislative power into peril, the Annenberg Public Policy Center’s survey on civic knowledge found that barely half of American adults can name all three branches of government, and 20 percent cannot name any rights protected by the First Amendment. Remarkably, these figures constitute  improvements  on the results of the previous 15 years of this annual survey. Even more troubling, the separate  World Values Survey  has found that since the 1950s, ever fewer numbers within each birth cohort in the United States has ranked it “essential” to live in a democratically governed country. Not even a third of Americans born in the 1980s think democracy is vital.  This state of affairs  follows prolonged disinvestment in the fields of history and civics: today, a new report reveals, federal spending per pupil in these subjects averages $0.05, whereas STEM education (science, technology, engineering, and mathematics) per pupil averages $50—a thousandfold difference in funding allocation. 

civic education

That report,  Educating for American Democracy , asserts that civic education needs massive investments of personnel, funding, attention, and energy in order to end this crisis threatening the future of the American democratic experiment—the conclusion of a commission funded by the U.S. Department of Education and the National Endowment for the Humanities.  Its report was assembled by a team of scholars and educators from Harvard ( Conant University Professor Danielle Allen , the current director of the Edmond J. Safra Center for Ethics, and Trumbull professor of American history Jane Kamensky , director of the Schlesinger Library), Tufts University (Kei Kawashima-Ginsberg and Peter Levine), Arizona State University (Paul Carrese), the education nonprofit iCivics (Louise Dubé), and the Arizona Department of Education (Tammy Waller). “We as a nation have failed to prepare young Americans for self-government,” the authors write,  “ leaving the world’s oldest constitutional democracy in grave danger, afflicted by both cynicism and nostalgia, as it approaches its 250th anniversary.”

The report offers a “road map, not a mandate or curriculum” for reform, Allen says: a flexible set of recommended approaches and a robust archive of materials meant to put a renaissance in civics and history education in reach of stakeholders at all levels, from local school boards and individual teachers to state and federal policymakers. Key conclusions of the project include: 

  • Schools should  integrate the teaching of history and civics  into a complementary curriculum. Especially at the high-school level, civics should not take the form of a “one semester and done” requirement.
  • States, districts, and teachers should  shift from breadth to depth . Many state civics requirements read as long lists of facts and principles to be memorized. States should reconceive educational goals in terms of open-ended questions (such as, “How have mechanisms of majority vote interacted with minority-protecting mechanisms over time?”) to stimulate analytical thinking rather than memorization (“What is a Constitutional Convention?”).
  • Instruction in all grades should not paper over disagreements on contentious civic issues, but rather teach how to “ cultivate civil disagreement and reflective patriotism ” in age-appropriate ways.
  • All levels of government should work together to enlarge and continuously support the nation’s corps of history and civics teachers (the report proposes the ambitious goal of  one million civics teachers by 2030 ), with robust mutual support networks and support from communities and states. University-level historians and political scientists should help put high-quality recent research into the hands of schoolteachers.

The report’s authors found it important to acknowledge forthrightly the fact that fiery ideological debates over the teaching of American history and politics have hampered advancements and improvements in civics and history at all levels. In the face of arguments over standards and narratives, inaction prevails. The authors mention that in 2009, the National Governors Association was able to establish shared standards for the Common Core in English and the STEM fields, but not in social studies, “because crippling debates over our history made compromises needed for a working debate impossible.” Consequently, the new report aimed to incorporate opinions from a wide spectrum of political beliefs: more than 300 individuals—progressive, conservative, and nonpartisan, including six former U.S. secretaries of education, both Republican and Democratic—as well as the perspectives of organizations ranging from the left-leaning New America Foundation to the right-leaning Jack Miller Center, and well-respected nonpartisan bodies such as the American Bar Association, the American Historical Association, and the Smithsonian Institution.  

The report urges the cultivation of “ civic friendship ,” terminology introduced by Allen in her 2004 book  Talking to Strangers: Anxieties of Citizenship Since Brown v. Board of Education . The authors define civic friendship as “the capacity and commitment to ‘fighting fair’—to engaging in debate with a commitment to honesty…[It] need not be characterized by ‘civility’ in the sense of polished manners, but it should be characterized by a commitment to the well-being of one’s interlocutor as well as oneself.” This capacity needs rebuilding from the ground up, according to the new report: schools are starting from a position of institutional atrophy and upheaval. “Students must be prepared today for a world of hyper-partisanship, of weak civic associations, and of social media instead of printed metropolitan daily newspapers,” the authors urge. 

Report coauthor Kei Kawashima-Ginsberg, who researches civic engagement, notes that as schools resume classroom teaching and heal after the disruptions caused by COVID-19, these questions take on renewed importance for communities and teachers. Crucially, civic-education reform will require support not just for students, but also for teachers within their communities. “[COVID-19] really affected how we thought about our instructional strategies. We couldn’t just include direct instruction with great content strategies for inquiry…we also had to take a step back to say, ‘Let’s think about our commitment to  all  students,’” she explains. Doing so requires that teachers create a good learning environment for students, and that, in turn, requires communities to support teachers. The report warns that previous efforts to reform social-studies education failed largely because they were not backed up by a commitment to  implementation:  to hiring teachers. And it entrusts communities with the responsibility of ensuring that teachers have access to proper training, certification, and continuing professional-development resources. “It demands collaborative effort,” says Kawashima-Ginsberg, particularly in light of “challenges that we have faced this past year, and that we may face in the future, too.” 

Educating for American Democracy  follows a related June 2020 report,  Our Common Purpose . That document arose from a project also co-chaired by Allen, together with Stephen Heintz, president of the Rockefeller Brothers Fund foundation, and Eric Liu, founder of Citizen University: the American Academy of Arts and Sciences’ Commission on the Practice of Democratic Citizenship.  Our Common Purpose  examined the structure of American democratic institutions and recommended sets of policies to help implement better the democratic prerogatives of the United States Constitution.

You might also like

Dean Rakesh Khurana in Harvard Yard

Rakesh Khurana To Step Down

The College dean will retire next June.

Massachusetts Hall

Alan Garber’s Opening Words

Harvard president welcomes students, foresees conflict in the year ahead.

five small sculptures of houses made of brass, suspended on posts and placed on the grassy shore overlooking Duxbury Bay

Among the Oyster Houses

Harvard students’ art installation nods at New England’s coastal farms.

Most popular

A young girl with pink headphones uses a tablet for an educational reading game at a classroom desk.

A Right Way to Read?

The science, art, and politics of teaching an essential skill

John Singleton Copley&rsquo;s <i>A Boy with a Flying Squirrel,</i> 1765

The Power of Patience

Teaching students the value of deceleration and immersive attention

House - Email

More to explore

 An illustration of a burning Earth breaking a rising red line graph, symbolizing the impact of climate change.

What is the Economic Impact of Climate Change on Global GDP?

The impact on global GDP is likely six times greater than previously estimated. 

Beau McCall, at left, wearing Button Jacket: Born in Philly, Made in Harlem, circa 1988, and his partner, Souleo, wearing Button Jacket: Stacked Sleeves, circa early 1990s-2021

Art Made Out of Buttons

Works by Harlem-based artist Beau McCall at Brockton's Fuller Craft Museum

Susan Farbstein smiles while standing outside in front of a building with columns and surrounding greenery, wearing a light blue blouse.

John Harvard's Journal

Susan Farbstein on Human Rights Law

Human rights lawyer on law’s ability to promote justice—and shape public understanding

How 3 States Are Digging In on Civics Education

BRIC ARCHIVE

By Stephen Sawchuk

What can states do to develop better citizens? CivXNow , a coalition of some 90 organizations spearheaded by the online curriculum group iCivics, has some ideas. The group recently unveiled a policy menu : Revise social science standards to prioritize civics. Align tests to them. Improve teacher training. Give youth a voice at schools and in local government .

K-12 education has been down this road before, without a lot of progress to show for it. An early-2000s push organized by many of the same players did not dramatically change the landscape.

What’s different from before, the coalition says, is the context. There are now success stories from states that have pioneered new civics education laws. There’s a research base on civics education that, while young, is increasingly robust. Finally, there is public recognition that something has gone deeply wrong in the state of American civil discourse, and that schools play some role in mitigating it.

Indeed, there are some signs of a legislative appetite for additional reforms. More than 80 pieces of civics education legislation were introduced across 30-odd states in the 2018-19 legislative session, according to Ted McConnell, the executive director of the Campaign for the Civic Mission of Schools, one of the CivXNow coalition members. And last year, the National Conference of State Legislatures counted nearly 115 civics education-related bills .

Getting the best ideas to the finish line is another story.

About the Citizen Z Project

U.S. public education is rooted in the belief by early American leaders that the most important knowledge to impart to young people is what it means to be a citizen. If America is experiencing a civic crisis now, as many say it is, schools may well be failing at that job.

To understand the role of education in preparing the next generation of citizens, Education Week began a series of articles, surveys, and projects in early 2018. This article is the latest installment in that initiative.

Some of the state legislation focuses on having all students take the same citizenship test used as part of the naturalization process—an approach most of the CivXNow coalition members believe is too narrow. (The Scottsdale, Ariz.-based Joe Foss Institute, which has pushed for the use of the test , is notably absent from the coalition.)

But inertia is probably the biggest challenge.

“It’s rare you’re going to have anyone against civics, but fundamentally it’s just not a priority,” said Shawn Healy, the director of democracy initiatives at the Robert R. McCormick Foundation, a key player in Illinois’ civics education efforts.

CivXNow says states can pick and choose from among the policies, though they’re most powerful in concert. It will also consider putting out model legislation in the future to guide states.

So how will the coalition know its push is succeeding?

“I wouldn’t measure success in one legislative session; it will take two to three years. We want to call back the time that’s been taken away from civics and social studies over the last 20-something years,” McConnell said, referring to the standards and accountability movement many civics advocates blame for focusing schools too narrowly on reading and math at the expense of history and civics. “ ... When a critical mass of states have done that, we’ll know we’ve had success.”

In the meantime, the civics and social studies lobby will need to beef up its own advocacy. Potentially, they could take a page from arts education advocates, who have been much more successful at making a research-based case for the importance of those subjects—such as by inserting the arts into the ubiquitous discussion of STEM (science, technology, engineering, and mathematics), now often called “STEAM.”

“My hope is that we can get our act together on that front,” Healy said. “It’s a been a bitter irony for me that the civics and social studies community has done a pretty bad job of advocating for ourselves.”

Below, Education Week briefly profiles three states at various stages of revising civics education requirements in their states—and what they’ve learned along the way.

florida

Florida: The Trendsetter

The Sunshine state is often lauded for its cohesive push for civics education, thanks to a 2010 law bearing the name of the legendary Supreme Court Justice Sandra Day O’Connor. The law required a new middle school course and an aligned test to measure civics knowledge that makes up nearly a third of each student’s grade in that subject. It covers four main prongs, including the origins and purposes of law and governments; citizens’ rights and responsibilities, the political process, and the organization and function of government.

The state remains one of the few to emphasize civics at the middle school level . In most states, formal civics education begins at high school. Whatever students get before that is taught within a generic social studies or history class—often in a nuts-and-bolts or overly sentimentalized , patriotic way.

In a sense, Florida’s traditional standards-and-assessment approach to civics owes something to the same reform movement that culminated in the federal No Child Left Behind Act—the test-heavy law that many civics experts now blame for reducing time spent on the subject. But there is some truth to the adage that what’s tested gets taught, and scores on the middle school test have risen on the exam across the state since its introduction in 2013-14, and just over 70 percent of students earn passing scores.

A lesser known factor in Florida’s work is the central role played by the Lou Frey Institute at the University of Central Florida. Although not formally part of the state’s K-12 education bureaucracy, the center has become the de facto clearinghouse for materials and teacher training for the course.

Even before the law had been signed, the institute was laying the groundwork. In 2009, it began developing model civics lessons for teachers. In 2010, the state legislature began appropriating funds to support those efforts, and in 2011, the state education department gave the institute a grant to run teacher professional development.

“I will tell you that building the kind of support system we have been for Florida is crucial to success,” said L. Doug Dobson, the Lou Frey Institute’s executive director. “Otherwise you just pass a law and clap your hands and say you’re done, and whatever happens, happens.”

Districts initially struggled to unlearn some of their former practices to cover the much more extensive content requirements: “The pacing was really a hurdle for us,” said Robert Brazofsky, the executive director for social sciences for Miami-Dade county. But now, the district has two staff members devoted to civics who provide in-school supports to teachers, and thanks to the testing data, they’ve been able to target schools with lower passing rates for extra help.

Now that the law is nearly a decade old, some in Florida are trying to get their arms around its impact. The Lou Frey Institute has worked with interested counties to informally survey students at the end of the middle school course on their civic beliefs and attitudes.

In Miami-Dade, Brazofsky said, most students surveyed agree with broad civic notions, like the importance of helping others in need, but there is still work to be done translating knowledge into lifelong behaviors and beliefs. For example, only about half of students surveyed said they thought it was OK for newspapers to publish freely without government approval.

“To really support and improve the civic attitudes of young people in my opinion, a test is a good thing to have, but it doesn’t always lead to the attitudes, beliefs, and dispositions you would want as an engaged citizen,” he said.

State Republican leaders, meanwhile, wants to double down on core civics knowledge. Gov. Ron DeSantis signed an order directing high schools to prioritize the U.S. Constitution , and recent legislation requires the state to review the civics course’s curriculum and test and recommend changes.

What impact that will have next on the Sunshine State’s approach to civics has yet to be seen.

illinois

Illinois: The Apt Pupil

Until 2015, Illinois had some of the weakest civics requirements around, leading to great differences in how the topic was being taught.

So when Illinois added a brand-new requirement for a semester of high school civics that year, those in the state knew it would take some kind of entity, like Florida’s Lou Frey Institute, to keep implementation on the rails in the state. Ultimately, that’s taken the form of a sort of gentleman’s agreement between legislators and the Robert R. McCormick Foundation, which pledged $1 million a year for three years to support the new learning—partly its own funding and the remainder raised from other philanthropies and donors.

Most of that has gone to support a crop of several dozen educators who work in concert with the state’s regional offices of education to supply training, resources, tips, and ideas to teachers about how to put the law into action.

For Bonnie Laughlin-Schultz, an associate professor of history and social science teaching coordinator at Eastern Illinois University, what’s groundbreaking about the law is not just the coursework requirement but also the specificity of the course content. The law says the class must include the topics of government institutions, service learning, simulations of the democratic process, and notably, discussion of “current and controversial events”—something even well-meaning teachers tend to ignore out of fear and discomfort.

“I think good social studies teachers were already doing many of those things, but it encouraged everyone to get on board,” said Laughlin-Schultz, who is one of the mentors in southeast Illinois. “Downstate, where I live, it gave teachers the ability to say: ‘No, I need to talk about controversial topics, it doesn’t matter what the political landscape is or whether administrators think it’s a good idea. It’s written into the law.’”

She said teachers have struggled most in understanding what service learning means in a civic education context.

“It’s not just a traditional ‘volunteer somewhere and keep a log of your hours’ thing—it is a much more intricate and authentic kind of experience. But that is intimidating to teachers,” she said.

To help them grasp the content, she hosts daylong civic engagement sessions at her university, where teachers and high school students from area schools meet to brainstorm steps they can take to address school issues, like presenting to the school board or writing a letter to a state representative. In effect, the workshops model the kinds of activities teachers can take back to their classrooms and enrich in a longer, more extended teaching unit.

Illinois’ entering high school freshman class of 2016, the first for whom the civics requirement took effect, begins its senior year this fall. In the meantime, Illinois is ready to expand its efforts. In May, the legislature passed a new law requiring a semester-long middle-grades civics course to complement the high school requirement. The bill, HB 2265, is currently awaiting Gov. J.B. Pritzker’s signature, and the McCormick Foundation is once again promising its financial support.

masssachusetts

Massachusetts: The New Kid

With Gov. Charlie Baker’s approval last November, the Bay State became the first state to require each middle and high school to include at least one student-led civics project .

Massachusetts’ law is among the most specific passed in decades, specifying not just content but a particular teaching approach: The idea of civics projects reflects “action civics”—having students research and use local civics channels to solve problems in their community.

It’s the culmination of two separate efforts in the state to improve civics that have fortuitously converged.

First, beginning in 2016, the state education department started revising its history and social science standards for the first time since 2003. The completed standards , unveiled in 2018, put a much heavier emphasis on civics learning throughout the grades and features a particular emphasis on civics in 8th grade. That grade’s standards now focus on the democratic foundations of the United States and their connections to the present, but isn’t a traditional, chronological history course.

Second, after several false starts, the civics-project legislation finally gained traction last year. It was heavily supported by a state coalition, most notably by Generation Citizen, a nonprofit, and the John F. Kennedy Library Foundation. The law authorizes a Civics Project Trust Fund, to be supported with state funds and outside grants, to support training and implementation on the projects. (A down payment on that new fund is currently caught up in budget negotiations: A Senate budget bill included $1.5 million for the fund while the House’s did not.)

It’s early days yet for implementation. The state education department has held regional sessions to familiarize teachers with the framework and has given out small training grants; in the future, it aims to supply some model lessons as well. And it’s now working to craft guidelines on how to approach the new project requirements, and how they might differ in an 8th grade and high school context.

Meanwhile, many districts have traditionally taught world history in 8th grade, so the move to civics in that grade beginning this fall will be a significant one, said Gorman Lee, the social studies coordinator for the Braintree district and a past president of the Massachusetts Council for the Social Studies.

There’s some looming concern about a potential civics assessment in the 8th grade. History and social studies haven’t been assessed in the state for about a decade. So far, the state is in the early phases of convening panels of teachers to begin developing test items, including some performance-based tasks . Teachers are closely watching to see how that might end up shaping their teaching.

“What is the state exactly expecting students to do? What might that assessment look like?” said Lee. “I get concerned that assessment becomes a ‘Who Wants to Be a Millionaire?’ multiple-choice test and puts students in a passive-learning mode.”

Perhaps that’s why, he says, educators feel two ways about the changes. They’re excited about renewed attention to their neglected field and they hope it will translate into increased district resources for social studies professional development and materials.

“But at the same time, they’re very cautious,” he said.

Image Credits: Getty

A version of this article appeared in the July 17, 2019 edition of Education Week as How 3 States Are Digging in on Civics Education

Sign Up for EdWeek Update

Schools of Political Studies

civic education

Back The Moscow School of Civic Education celebrates its 20th anniversary

The Moscow School of Civic Education celebrates its 20th anniversary

 20 years ago, on 4 April 1993, the Moscow School of Civic Education held its first seminar on "Politics, economics and national relationships". For the past two decades, the School has contributed to the objective of transforming Russia into a truly open and democratic civil society which functions effectively.

  • Diminuer la taille du texte
  • Augmenter la taille du texte
  • Imprimer la page

  Schools of Political Studies

 association of sps (asps) ,   sps @ world forum for democracy,   sps leaflet.

civic education

Advertisement

Advertisement

Developing civic consciousness in Russian higher education: an institutional case study

  • Published: 17 November 2022
  • Volume 86 , pages 1049–1064, ( 2023 )

Cite this article

civic education

  • Radomir Ray Mitic   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-3982-1055 1  

464 Accesses

10 Altmetric

Explore all metrics

This mixed-methods ethnographic case study examines the socio-historical origins and current lived experiences of students at one Russian university to understand the role of a university education as an environmental factor in the development of a civic consciousness. Findings suggest that the institution has attempted to introduce liberal civic education reforms while competing with a system-wide civic passivity developed during the Soviet era. At the same time, the institution is balancing political neutrality and social development to effectively execute its mission in spite of increasing state control. Student voices suggest that human capital development remains a top priority, whereas civic development has been limited. This case study serves as a cautionary tale in light of oppression and compromises that higher education institutions have to make with the state. Moreover, countries with a similar Soviet legacy of an atrophied civic society can look to modest reform efforts to engage individual students in a way that can promote civic participation so long as the state allows civic development to occur. This paper also addresses the implications of higher education’s role within the context of the 2022 Russian invasion of Ukraine.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save.

  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime

Price includes VAT (Russian Federation)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Rent this article via DeepDyve

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

civic education

More-Than-Civic: Higher Education and Civil Society in Post-Industrial Localities

civic education

Counter-Hegemonic Higher Education in a Remote Coastal Region of Brazil: The Federal University of Southern Bahia as a Case Study

civic education

Deciphering China’s higher education outreach paradigm in Southeast Asia: can a neo-tributary perspective work?

Explore related subjects.

  • Artificial Intelligence

Altbach, P. (2016). Two central obstacles to Russian academic excellence. International Higher Education, 87 , 20–22. https://doi.org/10.6017/ihe.2016.87.9508

Article   Google Scholar  

Baskerville, S. (2019). Academic freedom and the Central European University. Academic Questions, 32 (2), 257–262. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12129-019-09793-6

Becker, U., & Vasileva, A. (2017). Russia’s political economy re-conceptualized: A changing hybrid of liberalism, statism and patrimonialism. Journal of Eurasian Studies, 8 (1), 83–96. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.euras.2016.11.003

Becker, G.S. (1994). Human capital: a theoretical and empirical analysis with special reference to education (3 rd ed.). University of Chicago Press.

Belokurova, E., & Vorobyev, D. (2020). Overcoming depoliticization: The 2014 local electoral campaign in St. Petersburg. International Journal of Politics, Culture, and Society, 33 , 203–220. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10767-019-9323-4

Blinova, B., & Gorbunova, Y. (2021). Value foundations of marginal political practices of youth. SHS Web of Conferences, 94 , 1–6. https://doi.org/10.1051/shsconf/20219403017

Bowman, N. A. (2011). Promoting participation in a diverse democracy: A meta-analysis of college diversity experiences and civic engagement. Review of Educational Research, 40 (1), 29–68. https://doi.org/10.3102/0034654310383047

Brand, J. E. (2010). Civic returns to higher education: A note on heterogeneous effects. Social Forces, 89 (2), 417–433. https://doi.org/10.1353/sof.2010.0095

Bushkovitch, P. (2012). A concise history of Russia . Cambridge University Press.

Google Scholar  

Casula, P. (2013). Sovereign democracy, populism, and depoliticization in Russia: Power and discourse during Putin’s first presidency. Problems of Post-Communism, 60 (3), 3–15. https://doi.org/10.2753/PPC1075-8216600301

Cerami, C. (2021). Open society, academic freedom and the rule of law: The mission of Central European University (CEU) 1991–2021. Nuovi Autoritarismi e Democrazie: Diretto, Istituzioni, Societá, 3 (2), 124–139. https://doi.org/10.13130/2612-6672/16917

Chankseliani, M., Qoraboyev, I., & Gimranova, D. (2021). Higher education contributing to local, national, and global development: New empirical and conceptual insights. Higher Education, 81 , 109–127. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10734-020-00565-8

Chia, Y. T., & Zhao, Z. (2020). Citizenship and education in China: Contexts, perspectives, and understandings. Chinese Education & Society, 53 , 1–2. https://doi.org/10.1080/10611932.2020.1716590

Colby, A. & Ehrlich, T. (2000). Higher education and the development of civic responsibility. In T. Ehrlich (Ed.), Civic responsibility and higher education (pp. xxi-xlii). American Council on Education/Oryx Press.

Creswell, J.W. & Plano Clark, V.L. (2011). Designing and conducting mixed methods research (2 nd ed.). Sage Publications.

Creswell, J.W. (2013). Qualitative inquiry and research design . Sage Publications.

Creswell, J.W. (2014). Research Design: Qualitative, quantitative, and mixed methods approaches . Sage Publications.

Dewey, J. (1916).  Democracy and education. Southern Illinois University Press.

Doyle, W. R., & Skinner, B. T. (2017). Does postsecondary education result in civic benefits? The Journal of Higher Education, 88 (6), 863–893. https://doi.org/10.1080/00221546.2017.1291258

Eaton, C., & Stevens, M. L. (2020). Universities as peculiar organizations. Sociology . Compass, 14 (3), 1–13. https://doi.org/10.1111/soc4.12768

Evans, C. (2017, September 28). University education makes you a better citizen. [Blog post]. https://blogs.cardiff.ac.uk/wiserd/2017/09/28/university-education-makes-you-a-better-citizen/

Finkel, S. On the ideological front: The Russian intelligentsia and the making of the Soviet public sphere . Yale University Press.

Freeze, G.L. (2002). Russia: A history . 3 rd ed. Oxford University Press.

Gaber, E., Polishchuk, L., Sokolov, K., & Stukal, D. (2019). Chronicles of a democracy postponed. Economics of Transition and Institutional Change, 27 (1), 99–137. https://doi.org/10.1111/ecot.12207

Guba, E. G., & Lincoln, Y. S. (1985). Naturalistic inquiry . Sage Publications.

Hauptmann, J. (2005). Toward a theory of civic engagement. https://pdfs.semanticscholar.org/6866/54e052b019edd761299160c29f2a140996a8.pdf

Holmes, A. G. D. (2020). Researcher positionality – A consideration of its influence and place in qualitative research – A new research guide. International Journal of Education, 8 (4), 1–10. https://doi.org/10.34293/education.v8i4.3232

Human Rights Watch. (2022). Russia criminalizes independent war reporting, anti-war protests. https://www.hrw.org/news/2022/03/07/russia-criminalizes-independent-war-reporting-anti-war-protests

Igantieff, M. (2018). Academic freedom and the future of Europe. Centre for Global Higher Education Working Paper No. 40. https://www.researchcghe.org/perch/resources/publications/wp40.pdf

Isaeva, E., Sokolov, A., & Tarusina, N. (2015). Gender and civic engagement in modern Russia. Annales. Series Historia Et Sociologia, 25 (3), 451–468.

Janesick, V.J. (2015). Peer debriefing. In G. Ritzer (Ed.), The Blackwell encyclopedia of sociology (pp. 1–2). Wiley. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781405165518.wbeosp014.pub2

Kaczmarska, K. (2019). Academic community and policymaking in Russia: Impact or detachment? Problems of Post-Communism, 66 (4), 240–252. https://doi.org/10.1080/10758216.2018.1520603

Kassow, S. D. (1989). Students, professors, and the state in Tsarist Russia . University of California Press.

Kliucharev, G. (2017, May 24). Civic engagement in Russia. [Blog post]. https://blogs.cardiff.ac.uk/wiserd/2017/05/24/civic-engagement-in-russia/

Kuh, G. D. (2008). High-impact educational practices: What they are, who has access to them, and why they matter . Association of American Colleges and Universities.

Kuraev, A. (2016). Soviet higher education: An alternative construct to the western university paradigm. Higher Education, 71 , 181–193. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10734-015-9895-5

Lai, C. S. Y., & Hui, P. C. L. (2021). Service-learning: impacts of learning motivation and learning experience on extended social/civic engagement. Higher Education Research & Development, 40 (2), 400–415. https://doi-org.proxy.library.nyu.edu/10.1080/07294360.2020.1756748 .

Ljubownikow, S., Crotty, J., & Rodgers, P. W. (2013). The state and civil society in Post-Soviet Russia: The development of a Russian -style civil society. Progress in Development Studies, 13 (2), 153–166. https://doi.org/10.1177/1464993412466507

Lott, J. L., II. (2013). Predictors of civic values: Understanding student-level and institutional-level effects. Journal of College Student Development, 54 (1), 1–16. https://doi.org/10.1353/csd.2013.0002

Marginson, S. (2017). The public good created by higher education institutions in Russia. Educational Studies Moscow, 3 , 8–36. https://doi.org/10.17323/1814-9545-2017-3-8-36

Mart’ianov, V. (2007). The decline of public politics in Russia: From public politics to political administration. Russian Politics and Law, 45 (5), 67–82. https://doi.org/10.2753/RUP1061-1940450504

Mayhew, M.J., Rockenbach, A.N., Bowman, N.A., Seifert, T.A., Wolniak, G.C., Pascarella, E.T., & Terenzini, P.T. (2016). How college affects students: 21 st century evidence that higher education works (Vol. 3) . Jossey-Bass

McMahon, W. W. (2009). Higher learning, greater good: The private and social benefits of higher education . Johns Hopkins University Press.

Book   Google Scholar  

Merriam, S. B. (1998). Qualitative research and case study applications in education . Jossey-Bass.

Mingazova, N. M. (2014). Modification of the active learning methods in environmental education in Russian universities. Proedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences, 131 , 85–89. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.sbspro.2014.04.083

Minobrnauki [Ministry of Education and Science]. (2014). Website of the ministry of education and science of the Russian Federation. http://www.mon.gov.ru .

Morgan, J. W., & Kliucharev, G. A. (2012). Higher education and the post-Soviet transition in Russia. European Journal of Education, 47 (1), 3–8. https://doi.org/10.2307/41343406

Pipes, R. (1974). Russia under the old regime . 2 nd ed. Penguin Books.

Platonova, D., & Semyonov, D. (2018). Russia: The institutional landscape of Russian higher education. In J. Huisman, A. Smolentseva, & I. Froumin (Eds.), 25 years of transformation of higher education systems in post-Soviet countries: Reform and continuity (pp. 337–362). Palgrave.

Chapter   Google Scholar  

Polterovich, V. (2000). Civic culture and economic transition in Russia. Social Science Research Network . https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1751841

Pusser, B. (2018). The state and the civil society in the scholarship of higher education. In B. Cantwell, H. Coates, & R. King (Eds.), Handbook on the politics of higher education (pp. 11–29). Edward Elgar Publishing.

Pusser, B., & Marginson, S. (2012). The elephant in the room: Power, politics and global rankings. In M. Bastedo (Ed.), The organization of higher education: Managing colleges for a new era (pp. 86–117). Johns Hopkins University Press.

Rouvinsky, R. (2021). Lawmaking in times of domestic and foreign-policy instability (the Russian experience). The Theory and Practice of Legislation, 9 (1), 117–139. https://doi.org/10.1080/20508840.2020.1841986

Rovers, J., Japs, K., Truong, E., & Shah, Y. (2016). Motivations, barriers and ethical understanding of healthcare student volunteers on a medical service trip: A mixed methods study. BMC Medical Education, 16 (94). https://doi.org/10.1186/s12909-016-0618-0

Russian Union of Rectors. (2022). Address of the Russian Union of Rectors. https://www.rsr-online.ru/news/2022-god/obrashchenie-rossiyskogo-soyuza-rektorov1/

Salmenniemi, S. (2010). Struggling for citizenship: Civic participation and the state in Russia. Demokratizatsiya, 18 (4), 309–328.

Samsonova, T. N. (2020). When will the “dawn of new civism” rise over Russia. Moscow State University Bulletin Series 18 Sociology and Political Science, 26 (3), 66–87.

Sanina, A. G. (2018). Patriotism and patriotic education in contemporary Russia. Russian Social Science Review, 59 (5), 468–482. https://doi.org/10.1080/10611428.2018.1530512

Seregny, S. J. (2000). Zemstvos, peasants, and citizenships: The Russian adult education movement and World War I. Slavic Review, 59 (2), 290–315. https://doi.org/10.2307/2697052

Shibanova, E., & Malinovskiy, S. (2021). Higher education in Soviet and Russian welfare states: Hybridization, continuity and change. European Journal of Higher Education, 11 (3), 273–291. https://doi.org/10.1080/21568235.2021.1945475

Smith, M.J. & Pangsapa, P. (2008). Environment and citizenship: integrating justice, responsibility and civic engagement . Zed Books.

Smolentseva, A. (2017a). Universal higher education and positional advantage: Soviet legacies and neoliberal transformations in Russia. Higher Education, 73 , 209–226. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10734-016-0009-9

Smolentseva, A. (2017b). Where Soviet and neoliberal discourses meet: The transformation of the purposes of higher education in Soviet and post-Soviet Russia. Higher Education, 74 , 1091–1108. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10734-017-0111-7

Surman, J., & Rossman, E. (2021). New dissidence in contemporary Russia: Students, feminism, and new ethics . Advance online publication. https://doi.org/10.1177/2336825X211067405

The Moscow Times . (2020, January 17). Top Russian university moves to ban political speech. https://www.themoscowtimes.com/2020/01/17/top-russian-university-moves-to-ban-political-speech-a68945

Tolstenko, A., & Baltovskij, L. (2018). Problems of civic education in Russia (practice and metaphysics). Espacios, 39 (46), 21. http://www.revistaespacios.com/a18v39n46/a18v39n46p21.pdf .

Tolstenko, A., Baltovskij, L., & Radikov, I. (2019). Chance of civic education in Russia. SAGE Open, 9 (3), 1–16. https://doi.org/10.1177/2F2158244019859684

University of California, Berkeley. (2019). SERU-International. https://cshe.berkeley.edu/seru/seru-international

Yepaneshnikov, V. V., Pugacheva, N. B., Goloshumova, G. S., Kuznetsova, V. V., Dobrovolskaya, L. V., Moiseeva, L. V., Garaganov, A. V., & Litvinenko, N. A. (2016). Pedagogical management of civil education in research university students. International Review of Management and Marketing, 6 (S2), 23–27.

Youniss, J., McLellan, J. A., & Yates, M. (1997). What we know about engendering civic identity. American Behavioral Scientist, 40 (5), 620–631. https://doi.org/10.1177/0002764297040005008

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author is grateful to the National Research University Higher School of Economics’ Semyonov Award and its funding that made this research possible.

This study was funded by the Semyonov Award from the National Research University Higher School of Economics (Moscow, Russia).

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Department of Education, Health & Behavior Studies, University of North Dakota, Education Room 390, 231 Centennial Drive Stop 7189, Grand Forks, ND, 58202, USA

Radomir Ray Mitic

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Radomir Ray Mitic .

Ethics declarations

Ethics approval.

This study was certified by the National Research University Higher School of Economics’ Institutional Review Board and deemed to conform entirely to ethical standards.

All participants signed informed consent statements prior to taking part in interviews.

Competing interests

The author declares no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher's note.

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Mitic, R.R. Developing civic consciousness in Russian higher education: an institutional case study. High Educ 86 , 1049–1064 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10734-022-00961-2

Download citation

Accepted : 03 November 2022

Published : 17 November 2022

Issue Date : November 2023

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/s10734-022-00961-2

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Russian higher education
  • Post-Soviet higher education
  • Civic engagement
  • Political participation
  • Student life
  • Find a journal
  • Publish with us
  • Track your research

Democracy Without Borders

Democracy Without Borders

STAY POSTED

  • Subscribe to our newsletter
  • Take action for global democracy
  • Support us with a donation

On the need of a democratic global government

civic education

Ahead of UN Summit of the Future, civil society presents own proposals

civic education

  • Visit our blog
  • Global Order

PUBLICATIONS

A world parliament: governance and democracy in the 21st century (2nd ed).

  • All publications
  • UN Parliamentary Assembly
  • UN World Citizens' Initiative
  • "We The Peoples" campaign
  • UN Rapporteur on Democracy

Program Areas

  • Our Organization
  • Mission Statement

International Team

  • Find our email here

OUT NOW: New edition of "A World Parliament"!

civic education

Inna Berezkina

Russia/lithuania, editor, contributor, programme coordinator, school of civic education.

Inna Berezkina is a programme coordinator, a contributor and an editor at the School of Civic Education. The school, one of Russia’s preeminent NGOs, was founded by Lena Nemirovskaya and Yuri Senokosov in 1992 as the Moscow School of Political Studies. The mission of the School of Civic Education is to contribute to the development of civil society in post-Soviet Russia, CIS countries and Europe by promoting ideas of responsible civics, democracy, advanced civil society and the rule of law. Inna Berezkina is a contributing editor at the web portal Sapere Online. Since 2021, she serves as an advisor at Democracy Without Borders.

civic education

Progress at a price: UN NGO Committee reforms yield mixed results

civic education

  • Necessary These cookies are not optional. They are needed for the website to function properly.
  • Statistics In order to improve the website's content, functionality and structure, based on how the website is used.
  • Experience In order to provide the best possible user experience. If you refuse these cookies, some functionality will disappear such as location-based redirection.
  • Marketing By sharing your interests and behavior as you visit our site, you increase the chance of seeing personalized content and offers.

IMAGES

  1. Civic Education

    civic education

  2. Primary Four

    civic education

  3. Civic Education : Free Practice

    civic education

  4. Lesson Note On Introduction To Civic Education: Meaning, Scope, Aims

    civic education

  5. Words Civic Education Image & Photo (Free Trial)

    civic education

  6. A Look at Civics Education, State by State

    civic education

VIDEO

  1. Civic Education Final Project

  2. CIVIC EDUCATION CLASS VII

  3. CIVIC EDUCATION 2024: REEDUCATION

  4. Civic education when it comes to elections

  5. Civic education 2023 internal paper, answers✍️

  6. Civic Education g12 GCE 2017

COMMENTS

  1. Civic Education

    Civic Education. In its broadest definition, "civic education" means all the processes that affect people's beliefs, commitments, capabilities, and actions as members or prospective members of communities. Civic education need not be intentional or deliberate; institutions and communities transmit values and norms without meaning to.

  2. The need for civic education in 21st-century schools

    The origins of civic education. The fact that children today across the country wake up in the morning and go to school five days a week for most of the year has everything to do with civic education.

  3. Home

    We prioritize students in low-income communities to help close the civic empowerment gap. Learn More. Please Give to Support Civic Education. Donate Today. Only. 0%. of Americans born since 1980 rate it essential to live in a democracy. 0 in 3. Americans say they might consider abolishing or limiting the Supreme Court.

  4. The Importance of Civics Education

    In 2018, the Massachusetts Board of Elementary and Secondary Education revised its history and social science standards, placing a greater emphasis on civics and introducing a new yearlong eighth-grade civics course. The legislation also passed a law that requires all students in eighth grade and high school to lead a schoolbased civics project.

  5. What does civics education look like in America?

    A high-quality civics education thus includes opportunities for students to engage in activities within the classroom that model what democratic processes look like, as well as opportunities to ...

  6. Center for Civic Education

    Learn about American constitutional government with free, self-paced, and instructor-led courses. Join the civics forum, access ebooks, lesson plans, and primary sources.

  7. What Is Civic Education and Why Is It Important?

    Civic education is not just about knowing government structures, but also about feeling empowered to participate in collective decision-making. The Carsey School of Public Policy at UNH offers degrees and initiatives to bridge the gap between policy and citizens.

  8. The State of Civics Education in the General Populace

    This deemphasis of civics education is also reflected in the various states' existing requirements with respect to civics education. Currently, 31 states require a one-semester high school civics course and only six require a full-year course. The remaining states either require some civics instruction but not as a separate class or have no ...

  9. Home

    Today, up to 145,000 teachers and 9 million students in all 50 states utilize iCivics' innovative and free resources. Your tax-deductible donation helps us further our reach and deepen our impact, ensuring the practice of democracy is learned and embraced by each new generation. iCivics is dedicated to advancing civic learning so young people ...

  10. A portrait of civics education in the United States: The 2018 Brown

    The 2018 Brown Center Report on American Education endeavors to answer these questions, and others, with three separate analyses of issues related to civics education. Chapter 1 analyzes trends in ...

  11. Educating for Democracy

    Civic education has declined as a result of the focus on other subjects, like STEM. This is beginning to change — legislation mandating state-wide civic initiatives was recently passed in Massachusetts and Illinois — but high- quality, equitable civics standards need to be adopted everywhere. Joining this fight can lead to large-scale change.

  12. The Civic Life

    The Civic Life builds on American University's strengths in civic education and engagement across numerous disciplines (ranging from politics to the arts to STEM to business) and provides the tools we all need to engage and solve problems with one another and across viewpoints, perspectives, and lived experiences. While we often talk about ...

  13. Fixing the Foundation: Civics Education Reform To Solve ...

    Civics education in high school is foundational in encouraging democratic engagement for the rest of one's life. If done correctly, it provides practical preparation for voting and helps form ...

  14. Home

    Civics for Life offers free, online micro-lessons, policy briefs, and resources on civics topics for multigenerational learners. Learn about the rights and duties of citizenship, the presidential primaries, civil discourse, and more.

  15. PDF Civic education

    Civic education is the provision of information and learning experiences to equip and empower citizens to participate in democratic processes. Learn about the elements, applications and tools of civic education, and how to plan, implement and monitor a civic education programme or activity.

  16. Civics Education Is How We Can Repair Our Democracy

    A merica's civic education crisis is not new, but it is becoming increasingly dire. New data released by the Department of Education—known as the Nation's Report Card and widely regarded as ...

  17. Why civics education is necessary

    Laqueenda Adu, a senior at Central High School in Philadelphia, shares her experience and perspective on the importance of civic education for young people, especially for communities of color. She explains how civic education can help students find their voices and use them effectively in the current racial climate and beyond.

  18. The Crisis in Civic Education

    That report, Educating for American Democracy, asserts that civic education needs massive investments of personnel, funding, attention, and energy in order to end this crisis threatening the future of the American democratic experiment—the conclusion of a commission funded by the U.S. Department of Education and the National Endowment for the Humanities.

  19. Civic education in the United States

    Learn about the history, goals, and challenges of civic education in the U.S. education system. Find out how civic education has evolved to incorporate digital media, participatory culture, and social issues in the 21st century.

  20. Civics

    Civic education includes the study of civil law, the civil codes, and government with especial attention to the political role of the citizens in the operation and oversight of government. [ 3 ] Moreover, in the history of Ancient Rome , the term civics also refers to the Civic Crown , to the Corona civica , which was a garland of oak leaves ...

  21. How 3 States Are Digging In on Civics Education

    State Policy Civics. Image Credits: Getty. A version of this article appeared in the July 17, 2019 edition of Education Week as How 3 States Are Digging in on Civics Education. As more states jump ...

  22. The Moscow School of Civic Education celebrates its 20th anniversary

    20 years ago, on 4 April 1993, the Moscow School of Civic Education held its first seminar on "Politics, economics and national relationships". For the past two decades, the School has contributed to the objective of transforming Russia into a truly open and democratic civil society which functions effectively.

  23. Developing civic consciousness in Russian higher education: an

    This mixed-methods ethnographic case study examines the socio-historical origins and current lived experiences of students at one Russian university to understand the role of a university education as an environmental factor in the development of a civic consciousness. Findings suggest that the institution has attempted to introduce liberal civic education reforms while competing with a system ...

  24. Business icon, champion of civics education honored

    Business icon, champion of civics education honored. By Jeff Stoffer. Aug 27, 2024 Aug 27, 2024. ... honor of his remarkable business achievements but for his passion and dedication to the cause of teaching young people civics, American history and pride in U.S. citizenship. "During the course of my business careers, I have received a number ...

  25. Inna Berezkina

    Inna Berezkina. Inna Berezkina is a programme coordinator, a contributor and an editor at the School of Civic Education. The school, one of Russia's preeminent NGOs, was founded by Lena Nemirovskaya and Yuri Senokosov in 1992 as the Moscow School of Political Studies. The mission of the School of Civic Education is to contribute to the ...

  26. UT accepting applications for School of Civic Leadership inaugural

    The University of Texas at Austin said it was accepting Fall 2025 applications for its inaugural class in the School of Civic Leadership. ... education, law, entrepreneurship and public life, but ...

  27. Justice Ministry Adds Moscow School to List of 'Foreign Agents'

    The Moscow School of Civic Education has become the 18th nongovernmental organization to wind up on the controversial list, which sees nonprofit organizations punished as part of a 2012 law if ...